News stories about legal cases involving polygamy, how many parents a child can have, what unmarried partners owe one another and other family law issues have frequently made headlines in recent years. Based on these stories one might be tempted to conclude that contemporary family life and family law are often at odds.
Indeed, in this study, McGill University law professor Robert Leckey shows that while Canadian family law has evolved considerably over the past few decades, social practices and family relationships have changed even more dramatically and have outpaced the legal framework for families. He argues that these laws regarding family relationships interact crucially with public programs, especially in terms of gender equality, income security and children’s well-being. Therefore, he says, a discussion of the appropriate role of government in relation to families requires a clear sense of the state of the law.
The study describes the changes to family law in Canada in the second half of the twentieth century and its broad outlines today (including federal, provincial, civil and common law regimes). The author first sets out the conceptual framework for the rest of the analysis, presenting four oppositions that are the source of tensions in family law: 1) public versus private law; 2) instrumental versus symbolic recognition of a given relationship; 3) formal versus functional recognition of a relationship; and 4) formal versus substantive equality.
Leckey reviews the changes to marriage and divorce law in the last 50 years, notably those to equalize spousal rights and duties. Looking at data on the economic roles of spouses, he finds that legislative equality in marriage and divorce has not produced economic gender equality to the extent expected. At the same time, marriage rates have declined, so fewer couples benefit from the current regimes.
While marriage remains the most common family form in Canada, the landscape of Canadian families reflects increasing pluralism. Indeed, the increased social acceptability of relationships outside marriage has diminished marriage’s claim to the position of sole legitimate family form, while increased access and recourse to divorce have made marriage less permanent.
Paradoxically, the legal response to greater pluralism in family forms has been to treat more couples like married spouses. Leckey explores the legal recognition of same-sex and unmarried couples and shows that legislators have tended to base their treatment of these nontraditional forms of union on the traditional marriage model. He argues that this focus on marriage can impede recognition of other forms of nonconjugal relationships. Quebec stands out in this regard, since the Civil Code is silent regarding the duties of unmarried spouses toward one another.
Finally, the author turns to parents and children and shows that in today’s legal regimes for recognizing parentage, there are contradictory concerns about genetic linkages, intention to parent and family stability. Having described how legal parental status is established and outlined parents’ legal rights and obligations when the family breaks down, the author then examines the implications of recognizing the parental rights and obligations of individuals who do not have full parental status.
Overall, the author argues that a coherent and sound family policy must strike a balance between the tensions within family law. These tensions, he says, are an inevitable feature of family law in a plural society. The key mission for policy-makers, in his view, should be to ensure that asymmetry or irregularity of recognition is an intended part of a larger policy plan, and not happenstance.
He also cautions that formal equality does not necessarily result in substantive equality. Indeed, despite significant law reforms to provide equality, economic disadvantage in certain types of families persists (for example, in female single-parent households). This reflects the limits of private law and the fact that, in many cases, the family resources are insufficient to support two households after unions break down, hence the need for robust social programs.
In concluding, Leckey discusses avenues for further legal changes, and he sets out guidelines for the design of public programs that support families. He makes several recommendations in relation to private family law. Quebec, for instance, should enact a reciprocal obligation of support on the part of de facto spouses who have had a child together. In addition, all the provinces should
In recent years, the family life of Canadians has collided repeatedly with legal definitions of family. January 2009 witnessed the laying of criminal charges for polygamy practiced in Bountiful, British Columbia (Matas 2009). The same month, a trial took place in Montreal in which a woman sued the multimillionaire she had once lived with, seeking $50 million of his assets and $56,000 per month in alimony. Her claim challenged the constitutionality of both Quebecâs family law and federal marriage law (Peritz 2009). In a path-breaking decision in 2007, an Ontario court declared a child to have a third parent.1 And it was only in 2005 that the Parliament of Canada made same-sex marriage possible across the country.2
Interestingly, despite the challenges and important legal changes to our understanding of family, Canadian law has no official definition of âthe family.â For lawyers, the family â in a circular way â is the aggregation of the relationships, rights and obligations connecting those individuals who are otherwise seen as forming a family. So the relationships and duties of parents and children form a legal family, but the relationships and duties of neighbours do not. Relations between married spouses and between parents and children have been family lawâs traditional preoccupations. But the boundaries can shift, and recognition of family relationships by contemporary laws exceeds these categories.
Legal rules in Canada currently recognize family relationships in many, often inconsistent, ways. Talk about family relationships can be confusing because the same words can take different meanings in one setting than in another (Kasirer 1999). The word âspouseâ may mean something different in an invitation to a party, in rules fixing eligibility for welfare and in rules imposing support obligations. Peopleâs definitions of family for themselves â how many pet owners view their domestic animal as a family member? â often differ from those in legal instruments. In a reminder that family practices can develop independently from legal rules, many same-sex partners referred to one another as âspouseâ years before laws recognized them as such. Moreover, institutions in the private sector, such as employee benefit plans or the social pages of a newspaper, may recognize commitments that the laws of the state will not.
Difficulties in defining families connect to policy debates as to how governments should treat families and what programs they should provide so as to increase the well-being of family members. In recent years, such debates have considered topics such as parental leave, income splitting and child care. These debates engage controversial questions about the role of the state, the best use of scarce resources and intergenerational equity. In ways often left implicit, these debates connect to family law because they take definitions of family relationships for granted. Legal rules identifying family relationships and establishing their effects form the background for government programs and interact crucially with them. Discussion of the appropriate role of government in relation to families thus requires a clear sense of the state of the law, both past developments and the current regimes.
With an eye on these policy debates, this study aims to provide such an understanding of the past and present state of family law. The remaining subsections of this introduction identify key concepts necessary for understanding family law and set out the paperâs two arguments and the content of the four principal sections.
Four oppositions weave through the study. They help make sense of the developments studied and indicate areas of tension.
The first, concerning the parties to whom laws are addressed, opposes private and public family law. Private law regulates the relationship between persons and between persons and property. Rights and duties operate between family members as a consequence of their relationships. Specifically, the private law of the family treats matters of status and property as between family members, especially parents and children, on the one hand, and between adult intimate partners, on the other. Public law concerns the relationship between individuals and the state. In the family context, it consists largely of the programs through which governments carry out redistribution and deliver goods and services to individuals by virtue of their family relationships. Government policies such as taxation and social welfare help produce the family in law (Diduck and OâDonovan 2006).3 In recent years, the public side of family regulation has become more prominent, partly driven by rights claims under the Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms (Harvison Young 2001). Yet regulatory schemes that define family relationships for distributive purposes, such as workersâ compensation, date back to the nineteenth century. As the study discusses, private regulation and public regulation of families connect, as when a welfare scheme requires a claimant to enforce all possible private claims for support.
The second opposition arises between different reasons for identifying family relationships. Some forms of family recognition are instrumental: they are the instrument for applying legal rights and duties so as to achieve some purpose. The private law of the family uses marriage as a means for imposing duties of mutual support. The public law of the family takes conjugal relationships as a signal of interdependence, making appropriate the conferral of a survivorâs pension. Both the private and the public laws of the family use the legal bond between parents and children for the imposition of rights and duties. By contrast, some forms of family recognition have noninstrumental or symbolic value â that is, whatever their use, the legal recognition of some family bonds is understood as intrinsically valuable. Such recognition celebrates or affirms the relationship in a way that exceeds the enforceable legal content. For instance, the quest for same-sex marriage concerned the symbolic value of marriage, not only its rights and duties (MacDougall 2001). To be clear, calling a form of legal recognition âsymbolicâ should not imply that it is unimportant. Symbolic recognition may be intensely important to individuals and groups, a point underlying the struggles for legal recognition of various parental and conjugal relationships.
The third opposition consists of different bases for recognizing family relationships. Some rules of family law attach consequences to relationships on a basis that is formal. The classic formal bases for recognizing family relationships are marriage and parentage or filiation.4 The contrasting basis for recognizing family relationships is functional â namely, that the individuals have functioned similarly to the members of formally recognized family relationships. Recognition of unmarried cohabitation and of sustained conduct as a parent are examples of the functional approach.
A functional approach often takes individualsâ conduct as an implicit commitment to the relationship.
The fourth contrast opposes not dimensions of family regulation, but political conceptions of equality.5 Formal equality refers to identical treatment of individuals who are similarly situated. It drives toward sameness of treatment, a background state of affairs against which individuals achieve different outcomes in the market. Substantive equality is concerned with securing equal respect for different individuals in a way that takes their differences into account.6 It can lead to respectfully designed differences that recognize and affirm individualsâ characteristics, often concerning itself with equality of opportunity, if not equality of result. The relation between formal and substantive equality animates key issues in family law. For example, legislative reforms have made men and women formally equal in marriage, but women disproportionately experience economic disadvantage on divorce. They also continue to carry out disproportionate amounts of caregiving. That is why this study examines how well legal reforms to produce equality have translated into actual economic equality by looking at patterns of domestic and market labour.
What are the relationships among the four oppositions? Separating them is important for analytical clarity. Nevertheless, they do not interact in wholly random ways: some groupings are more common than others. The formal bases for recognizing relationships, such as marriage and filiation, are creatures of the private law; they usually engage both instrumental and symbolic dimensions. By contrast, the functional bases for recognizing relationships usually engage only the instrumental dimension. Public-law regimes typically recognize relationships for instrumental purposes, often using formal as well as functional means. It may be justifiable for law and policy to depart from such typical alignments, but, as discussed below, a departure from this pattern can also signal a potential incoherence in policy.
Before proceeding, a word about the structure of this field of law is in order. The Constitution Act, 1867 divides legislative power over the family, granting the provincial legislatures exclusive jurisdiction over family matters generally as part of their power over property and civil rights in the province, while assigning exclusive jurisdiction over marriage and divorce to Parliament. Another key constitutional feature is that the civil law provides the fundamental private law in Quebec, while the common law does so in the other provinces. These arrangements lead to the possibility that family will be defined differently in the two orders of government as well as from one province to the next. The chief sources of family law are the federal statutes and regulations, which apply across the country; the statutes and regulations of each province â in Quebec, the Civil Code; and the judgments of courts interpreting and applying those laws. The Supreme Court of Canada is the highest judicial authority for federal and provincial law. In principle, the Courtâs judgments relating to federal laws apply in all provinces, although it is sometimes thought that the distinctness of Quebecâs civil law of the family should condition the application of those judgments in that province. By contrast, when the Court interprets a provincial law or rules on a Charter challenge to such a law, its ruling does not apply directly in other provinces, although the principles emerging from such a judgment are highly relevant to other provinces, provided their own laws are sufficiently similar to the one considered. Since assessments as to the relative similarity or distinctiveness of provincial laws can vary, the impact of a Supreme Court judgment concerning a law from one province on the law of another can be a matter of considerable debate. In the light of this background, this study necessarily discusses both provincial and federal law and attends to both commonand civil-law regimes of the family in Canada. For simplicityâs sake, for most purposes it takes Ontario as a representative common-law province.
Adopting a legal perspective, this study surveys Canadian family law. It provides a nutshell account of changes to that law in the twentieth century, lays out the broad outlines of family regulation today and sets out the legal rules in an empirical context of data on family practices. It traces the four oppositions identified above through the field of Canadian family law.
In the course of this survey, the study advances two arguments. The first draws together the opposition between private and public family law, instrumental and symbolic reasons for recognizing relationships and formal and functional bases for doing so. At first blush, the varying rules and approaches might be taken as indicating a disorderly field or âchaosâ (Dewar 1998). Yet, however unruly the mass of rules and principles might appear, some order can be discerned. The variety of approaches point, collectively, to the insight that a meaningful and coherent family policy must attend, explicitly and simultaneously, to families as a matter for both private law and public law. It must also use formal as well as functional bases for recognizing relationships, ones that acknowledge the need for symbolic recognition of some relationships as well as, instrumentally, the importance of addressing the needs that arise from those and other relationships. The argument is not that the tension of these oppositions can be overcome; rather, such tension is an inescapable feature of family regulation in a plural society. A subsidiary to this argument about the multiple dimensions of family law is the striking contrast that will emerge in the case of Quebec, between that provinceâs progressive and prominent public policy in family matters and a restricted definition of the family in its private law that is arguably out of line with social practices.
The second argument is that law reform and family life in Canada show that formal equality does not necessarily bring about substantive equality. This observation does not call for rejecting formal equality. Indeed, the attainment of formal equality in many areas of family law has been an important step forward. But the observation underscores formal equalityâs limits, especially within the private law of the family. The ways in which economic imbalance has survived the legal equalization of different family members â wives to husbands, children born outside marriage to children born within â highlights the need for a robust family policy, on the public-law side, in order to realize Canadian societyâs commitment to substantive equality.
Both arguments unfold across the paperâs four main sections. The next section focuses on marriage and divorce. With an eye primarily on opposite-sex married couples, it provides a brief historical survey of the reforms of the past decades and addresses the contemporary regime during the relationship and afterwards. The third section surveys legal responses to the family practices of unmarried, opposite-sex cohabitants and of same-sex couples, both located outside traditional marriage. The fourth section traces the recognition of parental status and its effects, as well as the uneven application of some such effects to nonparents. Both the third and fourth sections show the grip of the past: the extension of family law has often remained in the shadow of the fundamental concepts of marriage and parentage. Although policy considerations emerge throughout the study, the last section focuses squarely on policy matters looking forward. It examines the limits of the private law of the family for securing the material well-being of family members, collects the recommendations for legal reforms set out throughout the preceding sections and presents lessons for revisions to public programs relating to families.
Marriage obviously has important social, economic, affective and, for many, spiritual elements. For present purposes, the starting point is marriageâs situation relative to the oppositions animating this study. Marriages attract consequences within regimes of private and public law. Legal recognition of marriage has instrumental value in the rights and duties it brings. It also has symbolic value in its public validation of a relationship. In terms of the bases for recognizing relationships, marriage is the paradigmatic case of formal ordering. It begins with a ceremony in which the partners exchange explicit, informed consent. Its conclusion is also formal: marriage is dissolved by the death of one spouse or by a judgment of dissolution. Assuming that the consent of spouses was free and informed, marriage seems consistent with individualsâ autonomy.
This section consists of four parts. The first recounts legislaturesâ implementation of formal equality for women within marriage, which can be seen as an improvement to the law of marriage. At the same time, the increased social acceptability of other forms of intimacy and the enlarged access to divorce can be seen, at least somewhat, as having displaced marriage as the sole form of legitimate union, resulting in âthe decline of marriageâ (Le Bourdais and Lapierre-Adamcyk 2004). The second part shows the gap between formal equality in terms of legal rights and duties within marriage contrasted with data on the economic roles of spouses. The third part sets out the regimes applicable on divorce, when the resources of one household are divided between two. The second and third parts indicate that the legislative adoption of formal equality has not produced substantive economic equality. The fourth part acknowledges the interaction of religious rules relating to marriage with the stateâs and identifies some of the resulting tensions and policy challenges.
Marriage has been the subject of much public debate. Indeed, there have been significant changes to the legal framework of marriage during the past century and a half. Developments have transformed three of its traditional hallmarks.
The first is the gendered character of marriage law. Husbands and wives historically had different roles, rights and duties during marriage. Statutes and common-law doctrines empowered men with decision-making authority on material and moral matters. In return for this authority, rules required men to support their wives. On marriage, a womanâs legal personality would merge into her husbandâs, so that men exercised womenâs civil rights â rights of property and contract, the initiation and defence of lawsuits â on their behalf. One consequence of this merger of legal personality was that it was impossible for one spouse to sue the other. In what was referred to as the married womanâs emancipation, reforms eventually equalized the rights and obligations of spouses during marriage. The process began in the common-law provinces in the 1880s (Girard 1990), though in Quebec not until the 1960s (Brisson and Kasirer 1996). At least formally, legislatures have now equalized the roles, rights and duties of spouses within marriage.
The second traditional hallmark is the status of marriage as the sole legitimate institution for sexual relations and child rearing. Historically, the legitimacy of marriage contrasted with the illegitimacy of other adult intimacy. Now, however, unmarried conjugality enjoys greater social acceptance than it did in the past (Milan, VĂ©zina, and Wells 2007, 8). Legal changes also took place, with legislatures repealing the rules penalizing unmarried relationships, notably ones nullifying gifts from one unmarried partner to another and prohibiting gifts made by will. This step eliminated lawâs explicit disapproval of cohabitation (Allard 1987). Moreover, as is recounted below, the legislatures of most provinces now subject unmarried opposite-sex couples to the same reciprocal duty of support as married spouses, and Canadian law no longer distinguishes between married and unmarried parents in setting out their rights and duties relating to their children.
The third hallmark is the intended permanence of marriage. Under Quebecâs 1866 Civil Code, for example, only the death of a spouse dissolved the marriage.7 Indeed, until Parliament enacted uniform legislation relating to divorce in the late 1960s, divorce laws across the country were a complicated patchwork of predominantly nineteenth-century English law.8 The increased availability of divorce in the last third of the twentieth century, however, diminished the permanence of marriage. It also aggravated the difficulty of disentangling the finances of husbands and wives. At one time, men typically held title to property acquired during the marriage. Consequently, the mere legal capacity of women to hold and manage their own property often failed to secure them anything like an equal share on the end of the marriage (Cullity 1972). The perceived injustice of womenâs exiting marriages with negligible assets, or none at all, generated pressure for reform of divorcing couplesâ property relations (Jacobson 1975). The 1968 Divorce Act set out in vague, discretionary terms the power of a judge to order one spouse to pay âcorollary reliefâ to the other,9 and, in the 1970s and 1980s, the common-law provinces and Quebec enacted a number of reforms that moved toward the principle of the sharing of the growth in the spousesâ wealth during marriage. Now, dissolution of a marriage requires limited resources to be allocated so as to make two viable households out of one.
The provinces regulate the symbolic validation of marriage in the form of its solemnization. They also regulate, instrumentally, the rights and duties of spouses during marriage, although provincial rules fill in the legal content of marriage in ways of which spouses may be only dimly aware. In all provinces, maintenance or family relations statutes â in Quebec, the Civil Code â set out the obligation of spouses to support one another.10 These obligations continue during a factual or legal separation.
Legislative announcements of spousal duties are cast in gender-neutral terms. Ontario law speaks of the necessity of recognizing the âequal position of spouses as individuals within marriage and to recognize marriage as a form of partnership.â11 This declaration is fully consistent with a specialization of labour that yields different amounts of income. Indeed, Quebecâs Civil Code contemplates that spouses may contribute toward the expenses of the marriage by domestic activities.12
However formally equal spouses may be in their rights and duties, significant gender differences persist in patterns of domestic and market labour. These patterns affect womenâs contribution to household income. Two-fifths (39.3 percent) of women in opposite-sex couples contribute one-quarter or less of the family revenue; 28 percent of women contribute more than one-half. Indeed, as table 1 shows, in households where there are no children, nearly one-quarter (23.6 percent) of women make no direct financial contribution to the family income, while another 37.9 percent contribute one-quarter or less of the coupleâs employment income, and 67 percent contribute 50 percent or less of employment income. The arrival of children, however, contributes significantly to the gendered differentiation of labour. In households with two children, 39.3 percent of women contribute one-quarter or less of the family income, while 76.3 percent contribute one-half or less. In families with three children, 79.3 percent of women contribute one-half or less of employment income.
Moreover, as figure 1 shows, women spend much more time out of the workforce after the arrival of their youngest child than do men, which affects the work experience and earnings of women relative to the men with whom they are in a relationship. As well, during the marriage, that role may condition the spousesâ choices, and may establish a pattern in which the woman has a larger role in child care; should the marriage end, that pattern may influence a judgeâs allocation of child custody. Family law regimes do not, explicitly, channel women toward domestic work over paid work relative to men. Yet the different roles spouses perform during marriage give critical importance to the distributive rules that apply when a relationship breaks down.
After Parliament enacted a divorce law in the 1960s, the divorce rate increased significantly: between 1971 and 1982, the annual number of divorces more than doubled, as did the divorce rate per 100,000 population (Gentleman and Park 1997, 54). The numbers and rates of divorce declined from 1982 to 1985, which suggests that some couples might have postponed their divorce in anticipation of legislation that would further liberalize access to it. Indeed, the 1986 Divorce Act made breakdown of the relationship the sole ground for divorce and reduced the evidence required to support the claim.13 During the two years after introduction of the new law, the numbers and rates of divorces rose dramatically: in 1985, there were 1,040.2 divorces per 100,000 legally married couples; in 1987, the peak year, there were 1,585.8 divorces per 100,000 legally married couples.
Divorce rates declined and levelled off in the 1990s, however, and the 1995 rate of 1,222 divorces per 100,000 legally married couples was not much higher than the 1982 rate of 1,215 (Gentleman and Park 1997, 55). For 2004, Statistics Canada reported a divorce rate of 10.6 per thousand legally married couples.14
Divorce produces effects of many kinds for spouses, children and extended family members. Its chief legal effect, one with instrumental and symbolic resonance, is the change in the marital status of the spouses. Its chief economic effect is the division of property and income between two households. Divorcing spouses may take into account a wide range of rules, including religious precepts, economic imperatives, social rules and state laws. Whether it is negotiated or, failing agreement, decided by a judge, a divorce settlement often draws on two bodies of legal rules: provincial legislation on the division of matrimonial property and federal divorce legislation on spousal support, child support and child custody.
The rules for the sharing of property typically grant each spouse an automatic entitlement. The point applies to equalization of family property in the common-law provinces and partition of the family patrimony in Quebec. The various provincial regimes are uniform in presuming an equal sharing of the increase in those assets during the marriage,15 although they differ somewhat in the basket of assets on which they operate (Payne and Payne 2006, 445-6; Pineau and Pratte 2006, 199-281). Crucially, the definitions of relevant property include pensions, although valuing them can be difficult (Martel 2003; Law Commission of Ontario 2008).16 The division of property between spouses reflects a legislative commitment to the idea that, whatever their role in the specialization of labour, spouses contribute equally to the marriage, which is viewed, unromantically, as a joint economic enterprise. It follows from this view that the spouses appropriately share its fruits. Indeed, legislation refers to âspouses,â without distinguishing husbands from wives, although provincial legislatures sought to remedy the injustice suffered by women who, on marriageâs end, faced economic precariousness. In crafting the rights and duties of married spouses, legislatures faced policy choices concerning the use of obligatory rules as opposed to rules the parties can alter by contract. These choices have resulted in an important distinction between common-law provinces, where spouses, by contract, may alter the rules of matrimonial property that apply to them,17 and Quebec, where spouses cannot exempt themselves from the rules of the family patrimony implemented in 1989.18 Both the common-law and civil-law regimes, however, recognize the importance of the matrimonial home, and it is possible, pending dissolution of the union, for one spouse to obtain an order for occupancy (Conway and Girard 2005; Pineau and Pratte 2006, 310-11).19
What is striking is that, simultaneously with the enactment of these rules on matrimonial property, the rate of marriage has declined. Throughout the 1960s, more than nine women out of ten would marry over the course of their life; by 2000, only 60 percent of women (and less than 40 percent of those in Quebec) were expected to marry at least once (Le Bourdais and Lapierre-Adamcyk 2004, 930). Thus, the proportion of adult unions affected by these rules on relationship breakdown has diminished significantly.20
Distinct from provincial regulation of spousesâ property, the federal Divorce Act addresses spousal support, authorizing a court to make an order that it thinks âreasonableâ for support of the other spouse.21 This discretion makes plain that, unlike the presumption of equal division of property, spousal support does not operate as of right. A spouse who claims support from the other must demonstrate entitlement to support as well as the appropriateness of the amount sought. Parliament listed three factors that judges must consider when exercising their discretion: the length of time the spouses cohabited, the functions performed by each during cohabitation and any order or agreement relating to support.22 Moreover, a spousal support order should recognize any economic advantages or disadvantages to the spouses arising from the marriage or its breakdown, apportion between the spouses any financial consequences arising from child care that are not addressed by child support, relieve any economic hardship of the spouses arising from the breakdown of the marriage and, insofar as is practicable, promote each spouseâs economic self-sufficiency within a reasonable time.
The broad outlines of the federal legislation require judges to fill in the details of the Canadian law of spousal support. Beyond the vague reference to âreasonableâ support, the legislation can be understood as reflecting several models of marriage and understandings of the basis of the obligation (Leckey 2002). Case law thus plays an especially large role. Moreover, while the legislative text has remained unchanged, the case law has changed significantly as the Supreme Court of Canada emphasizes one aspect of support, then another (Rogerson 2004). In 1992, in its landmark judgment in Moge v. Moge,23 the Court ordered support to a former wife who, though nearly 20 years had passed since the couple had separated, was still unable to support herself. The Court held that no single factor or objective takes priority â that is, in appropriate circumstances, the need to promote the partiesâ self-sufficiency did not rule out long-term support. The judges held that the Divorce Act requires a fair and equitable distribution of resources to alleviate the economic consequences of the marriage or of its breakdown. In particular, the Court underscored the importance of spousal support for compensating a spouse for losses connected to the marriage.
In 2001, in response to concerns about the uncertainty in the law of spousal support, the Department of Justice asked two specialists in family law, Rollie Thompson and Carol Rogerson, to develop Spousal Support Advisory Guidelines. The guidelines do not have the force of law; rather, they are intended as a starting point for negotiations by spouses and their lawyers and for judges. The intention was that the guidelines would reflect the existing law, rather than change it.24
Spouses typically negotiate a global settlement, dealing simultaneously with child custody, property division and spousal support. Such negotiations, however, may disadvantage women: in exchange for concessions they see as benefiting the children, women may concede their economic entitlements (Martin 1998).
Indeed, despite the concern for equality in the distributive rules of family law, recently divorced or separated mothers remain financially worse off than recently divorced or separated fathers. As table 2 shows, 44 percent of recently divorced or separated mothers have an annual personal income of less than $30,000, contrasted with 19 percent of recently divorced or separated fathers. Moreover, 28 percent of recently divorced or separated mothers have an annual household income of less than $30,000, compared with 12 percent of recently divorced or separated fathers. Further, as table 3 shows, there is a high incidence of low income for families with children headed by a single female parent. Despite improvements over the past 20 years, the economic disadvantage of single-parent families headed by women has persisted. The causes are doubtless complex, and the picture necessarily must take into account the rules on the support of children (discussed in a later section). Before taking up that matter, however, it is appropriate to consider problems raised by the contemporary pluralism of Canadian families, which has effects both within marriage and beyond.
So far, the study has treated marriage primarily from the perspective of state law, viewing marriage as a civil institution. This section, however, addresses sources of friction between religious family practices and state regimes by looking at the issues of religious dispute resolution in the family setting and polygamy.25
To what extent should legislatures and policymakers care about the influence and use of religious norms as family members attempt to resolve disputes? Recent public debate has focused on recourse to religious, notably Muslim, norms and on the use of religious arbitral forums. The suitability of religious norms and forums, however, must be contextualized in relation to the scope for private ordering in family matters more generally.
Provincial and federal regimes present considerable scope for parties to negotiate and conclude agreements that depart from the legislated default rules (Roy 2006a; TĂ©trault 2007b).26 Where children are concerned, other rules apply, and courts assume a greater supervisory role. There is also significant scope in some provinces for alternative dispute resolution outside courts, through mediation and arbitration.27 Use of these possibilities by Christians on the ostensibly âsecularâ ground of individual choice typically attracts little media or other attention, even if one spouse receives a distribution that is less than she would have obtained under the default rules of the state regime or in a court.
By contrast, recourse to rules deriving from Islamic sources and arbitration in a religious forum have caused much more controversy (Macklin 2005; Ryder 2008, 104-6). In reaction to public outrage over the possibility of so-called sharia courts, Ontario amended its law in 2006 so as to specify that family arbitrations may be conducted only in accordance with the law of Ontario or of another Canadian jurisdiction (Razack 2007; Weinrib 2008).28 Some scholars have rightly expressed concern that rules prohibiting the recourse to religious norms or the use of religious arbitral forums are likelier to drive practices underground than they are to eradicate them (Macdonald and Popovici 2007; Shachar 2008). Moreover, while religious arbitration may have no legal force in Ontario, mediation remains a viable method for couples intent on using religiously based dispute resolution mechanisms. The mediation option suggests that ânothing has fundamentally changed for Muslim women whose vulnerability to bad faith husbands and patriarchal imams was the central concern of opponents to Sharia arbitrationâ (Emon 2009, 420). The shift underground of practices following such a legal reform is notoriously difficult to track and calls for careful empirical inquiry.
While the ways in which religious practices may adapt to law reforms is a concern, the larger point is that a focus on religious norms and arbitration in the resolution of family disputes risks exaggerating the distinctiveness of religion for family policy. In fact, divorcing spouses may exact and receive less than their statutory entitlement for a host of reasons, some of which rightly may engage public policy. The hostile reaction to the idea of religious arbitration in Ontario seemed, however, without conclusive evidence, to take religious norms as the most pressing reason a divorcing woman might claim and receive less than her fair share of household resources. Moreover, criticisms of religious arbitration forums unfolded against an unfounded assumption that the civil courts are easily accessible and affordable for family justice; in reality, many barriers prevent individuals â be they Muslims, Jews, members of another religion or nonbelievers â from going to court to enforce their rights (Macdonald 2003). For family policy, the pressing issue is the access of vulnerable individuals, especially women, to information and other support services as they undergo relationship breakdown. These needs transcend enculturation in one religious tradition or another.
The second point of friction at the intersection of religious marriage and state law relevant for present purposes is polygamy. The practice of polygamy poses difficult policy questions in fields such as criminal law, family law, immigration, taxation and social policy (see, for example, Bailey et al. 2005; Campbell 2005). Separating the strands in reference to this paperâs key oppositions helps clarify the issues for debate, although it is only a preliminary step.
In the public-law terms of the criminal law, practising âany form of polygamyâ or entering into âany kind of conjugal union with more than one person at the same timeâ remains an offence punishable by up to five years in prison.29 The charges recently laid in Bountiful, British Columbia, likely will lead to a testing of this criminal prohibition against the guarantee of religious freedom in section 2(a) of the Charter (Meissner 2009). Turning to private law, with an instrumental focus on the distribution of resources among family members, the drafters of family law must consider whether to enforce support duties arising from a polygamous marriage validly celebrated abroad. For example, Ontarioâs Family Law Act includes, in its definition of âspouse,â a marriage that is actually or potentially polygamous if valid where it was celebrated.30 An individual in such a polygamous marriage could seek an order in Ontario for support from another âspouse.â Distinct from this distributive question, another private-law matter engages family lawâs symbolic dimension: should the federal definition include polygamous unions as civil marriages? What, if anything, does the recognition of same-sex marriages entail for polygamous unions (Leckey 2007b; Galloway and Matas 2009)?
Additional instrumental considerations play out in public-law fields such as immigration, taxation and welfare policy. The immigration problem includes whether rules relating to sponsorship and family reunification should take into account the bonds of foreign polygamous marriages. Taxation and social policy issues include the extent to which the rules defining tax credits and entitlements should take into account polygamous marriages. What is the appropriate posture in relation to a religious polygamous marriage of a state regime that confers a benefit on a contributorâs surviving married or common-law spouse? The example of Bountiful shows that at least some people in Canada practice polygamy. This fact should prompt policymakers to consider the extent to which their role is to respond to existing family practices as opposed to directing them.
This brief overview of some frictions between civil and religious marriage law sets the stage for discussion of another kind of pluralism â that of adult relationships outside marriage. The connection is that, in both cases, difficulties can arise from a policy focus that takes the civil marriage regime as paradigmatic.
As table 4 shows, married-couple families remain the most common family structure, constituting 68.6 percent of all families in the 2006 census (down from 70.5 percent five years earlier). Within the set of married-couple families, the largest family structure is that of married couples with children ages 24 and under, representing 34.6 percent of total census families (Milan, VĂ©zina, and Wells 2007, 11). Collectively, however, Canadian families are more plural in form than they were several decades ago. The census in 2006 for the first time enumerated more unmarried people ages 15 and over (51.5 percent) than legally married people; 20 years earlier, 38.6 percent of the population ages 15 and over was unmarried (Milan, VĂ©zina, and Wells 2007, 19). How do these forms of family outside traditional marriage fit into the landscape of family law?
In 2001, the Law Commission of Canada collected four legal models used for regulating adult personal relationships: marriage, private law, ascription and registration (xvi). Box 1 summarizes them.
With reliance, in varying measures, on the models of marriage, ascription and registration, Canadian family law in recent decades has gradually recognized two new kinds of couples beyond the traditional, married, opposite-sex couple.31 One is the unmarried, cohabiting, opposite-sex couple,32 known in Quebec as the de facto union. The other is the same-sex couple.33 The legal recognition of these types of couples is the product of judicial and legislative activity. Together, their stories show more concretely the promise and risks of the four legal models. They also provide revealing case studies of the movement and tension between dimensions of family law: public law and private law, instrumental and symbolic, and formal and functional. These examples of family law pluralism also connect with the political ideals of formal and substantive equality, measured within individual couples and from one group of couples to another.
The discussion develops across three subsections. The first two address, respectively, unmarried couples and same-sex couples. The third makes explicit the grip of the past in the underlying assumption of marriage as the paradigmatic adult relationship.
From the 2001 census to that in 2006, the number of unmarried-couple families grew by nearly one-fifth (18.9 percent), a rate more than five times faster than that for married-couple families (see table 4). In 2001, unmarried-couple families accounted for 13.8 percent of all census families; by 2006, they were 15.5 percent. Two decades ago, however, they accounted for only 7.2 percent of all census families (Milan, VĂ©zina, and Wells 2007, 9). This sustained increase in the incidence of unmarried couples hints that they might present a matter for further attention by policy-makers. Indeed, as table 5 shows, unmarried cohabitants have a much higher probability of union disruption than do married couples.
Most provincial legislatures have used the ascription model for unmarried couples. In the common-law provinces, legislation requires unmarried cohabitants to support each another; the duty persists after cohabitation ends.34 As evidenced by legislative debates, the objective in most instances was not primarily to recognize the intrinsic worth of unmarried cohabitants as an identity group or to affirm their equality to married couples, but, instrumentally, to palliate the vulnerability of women who had lived with men with a view to reducing claims to public assistance.35
Although this policy choice has been widely adopted, analogizing unmarried and married couples for the assignment of duties can cause difficulties and surprises. Unlike married spouses, unmarried cohabitants have no formal marker of their relationship; legislatures wishing to regulate them thus need a proxy for their commitment. A typical choice is continuous cohabitation for a given period, such as three years. An alternative basis may be living âin a relationship of some permanenceâ and having a child together.36 A criterion of cohabitation for a specified period, however, is more likely to cause disputes over evidence than a criterion of marriage or registration. On the breakdown of the relationship, members of an unmarried couple may disagree on when they really began living together and, thus, whether they crossed the statutory threshold.
Another surprise can come when the partners stop living together. Marriage brings a legal status that persists even when the spouses have separated; the legal bond of marriage survives until dissolved by the death of one spouse or by a divorce judgment. By contrast, a cohabitation relationship, which is recognized on a functional basis, does not survive in a comparable way the physical separation of the parties and the intention of one of them that it should end. Thus, by terminating a cohabitation relationship, an individual loses his or her claim, for instance, to a survivorâs pension under the Canada Pension Plan on the partnerâs death. In other words, government programs treat a former common-law partner like a divorced spouse, not like a separated married spouse.37
Alone among the provinces, Alberta has used the ascription model to attribute support obligations to a set of relationships larger than conjugal cohabitants. That provinceâs scheme of âadult interdependent relationships,â adopted in 2002, includes relationships outside marriage in which two persons share each otherâs lives, are emotionally committed to each other and function as an economic and domestic unit. There is no sexual requirement.38 Alberta designed this scheme so as to comply with its constitutional obligations regarding same-sex couples arising from a legal case known as M. v. H.39 After the judgment in that case, the provincial government resisted elevating same-sex couples alone to a position equal to that of opposite-sex cohabitants (Alberta Law Reform Institute 2002), which suggests that, in its view, the instrumental extension of rights and duties to gay and lesbian couples on a functional basis risked validating them. Consequently, the government drafted a more widely cast regime that includes not only same-sex cohabitants, but also some nonconjugal couples who live together, such as two friends. The regime has the advantage of loosening the legislative grip on conjugality as the key indicator of legally relevant relationships (Cossman and Ryder 2001), but it also risks surprising individuals who do not see themselves as tacitly assuming obligations toward a person with whom they live (Bala 2003, 903). Because the scheme is relatively recent, its wider impact remains to be seen.
On the question of spousal support for unmarried couples, Quebec provides a glaring contrast. As in the other provinces, public-law legislation enacting social programs in Quebec, such as workersâ compensation, treats de facto spouses similarly to married spouses in most respects (TĂ©trault 2005, 549-51) â that is, for instrumental purposes, the public law of the family recognizes unmarried couples on a functional basis. Under the private law, by contrast, de facto spouses, as such, owe each other nothing (Moore 2003, 76-86) â in lawyerly jargon, they are legal strangers one to another. This state of affairs reflects a legislative choice to confine the family regulation within the Civil Code almost entirely to those relationships recognized by formal means. The result is that, in Quebec more than in any other province, the set of family relationships recognized by the private law for instrumental purposes is identical to the set recognized for symbolic purposes.
The Civil Codeâs silence regarding the duties of de facto spouses is especially striking given the prevalence of unmarried cohabitation in Quebec.40 According to the 2006 census, unmarried couples represented over one-third (34.6 percent) of all couples in the province, a much higher proportion than in the other provinces and territories (13.4 percent).41 The increase in the incidence of unmarried couples in Quebec from 2001 to 2006 was 20.3 percent (Milan, VĂ©zina, and Wells 2007, 35). As table 5 shows, the relationships of unmarried couples in Quebec appear to be somewhat more stable than those of unmarried couples elsewhere in Canada, but the likelihood of the disruption of such relationships is still three and a half times higher than for married couples elsewhere in Canada.
Matrimonial property provides a contrast with the support regimes in force in all provinces but Quebec. Most provinces restrict their matrimonial-property regimes to married couples and, typically, no rules call for the sharing of assets when cohabitation ends. In the late 1990s, a former cohabitant in Nova Scotia challenged the constitutionality of her provinceâs exclusion of unmarried couples from its matrimonialproperty regime and won her case in the provincial court of appeal. Following that judgment, the legislatures of Manitoba and Saskatchewan amended their statutes so as to include unmarried couples in their matrimonial-property regimes.42 On further appeal, however, the Supreme Court of Canada reversed the holding that restricting the regime of matrimonial property to married couples discriminated against unmarried couples. In 2002, in Nova Scotia (Attorney General) v. Walsh,43 it upheld the distinction on the basis that only married couples had chosen to subject themselves to the onerous rules of property division. The class of unmarried cohabitants, held the majority of the Court, was diverse and it was impossible to presume their consent to the regime.
Consequently, unless they have made arrangements by contract, unmarried cohabitants have relatively little protection in property matters. They may make a claim under the general private law, however, and have had modest success in claims of unjust enrichment (Lefrancçois 2005, 51-5; Payne and Payne 2006, 60-1).44 Such claims require case-by-case demonstration of three elements: impoverishment on the part of the claimant, a corresponding enrichment on the part of the respondent and an absence of juristic reason, such as a contract, for the wealth transfer. Claims in unjust enrichment are most useful where one partner has contributed tangibly to significant property owned by the other. Overall, however, the recourse to claims of unjust enrichment is far from a full substitute for the equalization of family property or partition of the family patrimony available to married spouses.
In addition to the use of the ascription model, several provinces provide registration options for partners who do not wish to marry or cannot do so. Registration schemes for domestic partnerships have been available since 2000 in Nova Scotia and since 2002 in Manitoba (Roy 2002b).45 Albertaâs regime, noted earlier as an instance of the ascription model, also has a registration component: two adults, including those who are related by birth or adoption, may enter into an adult interdependent partnership agreement and thus may invoke the provisions that would apply by ascription to couples who satisfy the statutory criteria.
Quebec enacted its own alternative to marriage, the civil union, in 2002.46 It is more than simply a registration scheme, however; drawing on the symbolic affirmation associated with marriage, the Civil Code refers to a civil unionâs âsolemnizationâ (Kasirer 2003). It is available to both same-sex and opposite-sex partners, and its rules incorporate the legal regime of marriage, including the obligatory rules of the family patrimony.47 Unlike marriage, however, which requires a divorce judgment, a civil union can be consensually dissolved by a notarized joint declaration by the spouses.48
At the time they were introduced, the registration schemes just noted provided a formal recognition option for same-sex couples who, under federal law, could not yet marry (Moore 2002b; Fisher et al. 2004). Now, same-sex couples are recognized within Canadian family law on footing identical to that for opposite-sex couples. As recently as 1995, however, in Egan v. Canada,49 the Supreme Court of Canada rejected a claim that Old Age Security, a distributive program structured by public law, discriminated unjustifiably on the basis of sexual orientation by excluding same-sex couples.
In contrast, the first major Charter success before the Supreme Court relating to recognition of samesex relationships concerned the private law of the family. In M. v. H.,50 the Court heard a claim of a former member of a lesbian cohabiting couple that it was sexual-orientation discrimination, contrary to section 15 of the Charter, for Ontario to ascribe a spousal-support regime to unmarried, opposite-sex couples while ascribing no such regime to unmarried, same-sex couples. The regime to which the claimant sought access reflected an instrumental goal of addressing womenâs economic vulnerability so as to reduce demands on the public purse. The claimant contended that, where the legislature recognized unmarried, opposite-sex couples on a functional basis, it should recognize same-sex couples on the same basis. The other woman opposed the claim, resisting the retroactive characterization of their relationship, on a functional basis, as marriage-like.
The Court agreed with the claimant. It referred to family lawâs instrumental and symbolic roles, and acknowledged that its judgment would reduce the claims on public resources by former members of same-sex couples. But, consistent with its case law on section 15 of the Charter,51 it framed its judgment as a glowing, symbolic validation of same-sex couplesâ worth and commitment (Cossman 2002a,b). Combining different bases for regulating family in an arguably problematic way, the Court used the language of dignity and recognition more typically associated with formal, consensual bases for regulation, such as marriage, than with the functional basis of ascription. In the Courtâs view, ascribing duties to unmarried couples without their consent upheld their dignity and enhanced their self-worth.
In response to M. v. H., Parliament and provincial legislatures brought their regimes in line with the Courtâs holding that distinctions between unmarried couples on the basis of sexual orientation were unconstitutional (Cossman and Ryder 1999).52 Ontario, for instance, added a new category, âsame-sex partner,â to its Family Law Act.53 Quebec replaced gendered definitions for couples in more than two dozen statutes with a gender-neutral definition of de facto union.54 Consequently, where spousal-support regimes attach to opposite-sex couples who live together, they also attach to same-sex couples who do so. The different forms of the legislative responses to M. v. H. â including Albertaâs innovation detailed above â show awareness that even the instrumental recognition of same-sex couples on a functional basis had symbolic resonance.
Several years later, the focus of advocacy shifted to marriage, with the next generation of claims squarely targeting the stateâs symbolic affirmation in the formal institution of marriage. Thus, recognition of same-sex couples as family for instrumental purposes in M. v. H. paved the way for their symbolic recognition (Leckey 2007d). Lawsuits in a number of provinces led to declarations that the opposite-sex requirement for marriage violated the Charter on the basis of sexual orientation.55 Parliament eventually passed legislation making it possible across the country for same-sex couples to marry civilly.56 Canadaâs recognition of same-sex couples has put it, along with countries such as the Netherlands, Spain and South Africa, at the cutting edge of family developments (Wright 2006; Bamforth 2007).
From a policy perspective, same-sex couples may have merged onto the general terrain of family law, but viewed in the light of the impact of same-sex marriage on public discourse, their numbers are not high, representing 0.6 percent of all couples in the 2006 census.57 Married same-sex couples, who amounted to 16.5 percent of all same-sex couples in 2006 (Milan, VĂ©zina, and Wells 2007, 12), have the benefit and burden of spousal support and division of matrimonial property. Unmarried same-sex couples fall under whatever legislative regime operates in their home province.
With the adoption of these instrumental and symbolic forms of recognition, it might be that sexual orientation is no longer a salient criterion for identifying policy challenges. The financial vulnerability of a same-sex partner after a long relationship with a specialization of labour may be the same as that of an opposite-sex spouse.58 Indeed, although one might suppose that same-sex relationships escape the negative effects for women associated with opposite-sex marriage, sociological inquiry shows that, over time, many same-sex couples assume a specialization of labour similar to that of opposite-sex spouses, one that is reflected in different earnings (Carrington 1999). Moreover, lesbian couples might be expected to exacerbate the impact of womenâs lower earnings relative to menâs: female same-sex couples might bear the brunt of a gendered labour market, with neither partner appearing in the better-paid category.
While the legal situation of same-sex relationships seems to have stabilized, the position of unmarried couples in Quebec has recently made headlines. As noted in the introduction, in January 2009 a trial took place in Montreal of a former de facto spouse who sought inclusion in federal and provincial marriage laws (Peritz 2009). With a view to receiving $50 million of her former partnerâs assets and $56,000 per month in alimony (distinct from the child support she receives from her former partner for their children), she made three constitutional claims. First, it was unconstitutional for the Civil Codeâs spousal-support regime not to include de facto unions. Second, it was unconstitutional for the Civil Codeâs family patrimony rules not to extend to de facto unions. This claim appears contrary to the Supreme Court of Canadaâs judgment in Walsh,59 although the legal context differs from that present in that Nova Scotia case (Leckey 2009a). These two claims required the court to find that it is discriminatory to apply an instrumental family policy to couples recognized formally but not to couples recognized functionally. The third claim was that it was unconstitutional for Parliamentâs Civil Marriage Act not to include, as married, partners who have lived together for three years. This claim engaged the symbolic affirmation associated with marital status, attacking the constitutionality of a status secured by exclusively formal means.
Given the resources available to both parties, and in particular the stated intent of the claimantâs lawyer to change family law, the case is unlikely to be settled for some time. But this lawsuit unfolds against a larger backdrop, and provides an occasion for reflecting on the appropriate treatment by lawmakers and policy-makers of relationships outside traditional marriage. In recent years, a number of scholars have called for revision of the legal position of unmarried couples in Quebec (Jarry 2008). Others, emphasizing liberty and choice, protest the illegitimacy of imposing duties on individuals without their consent (Roy 2002a, 883; Mrozek 2009). What issues should be borne in mind for policy reflection?
A significant factor is the impact of the existing rules on children. A focus on the choice or autonomy of adults allows little space in which to discuss the effect of parentsâ marital status on their children. In determining the duties of parents to their children, Canadian legislatures do not distinguish married from unmarried parents, as we will see in a later section. Yet, in most provinces, the legal treatment of unmarried cohabitation does result in disadvantages for children whose parents are not married. The protections of marriage â chief among them the possibility of one spouse securing exclusive possession of the matrimonial home â indirectly benefit the children of married parents over those of unmarried parents.60
How many children are affected? In Canada, the proportion of married couples with children ages 24 and under far exceeds that of unmarried couples with children those ages (34.6 percent versus 6.8 percent). Nevertheless, significant numbers of children are raised in unmarried-couple families: according to the 2006 census, of all children ages 14 and under living in private households, 14.6 percent lived with parents in a common-law union, more than triple the proportion of two decades earlier (Milan, VĂ©zina, and Wells 2007, 11, 24). Concerns about the effects of parentsâ unmarried cohabitation on their children are increasingly raised in Quebec (Goubau, Otis, and Robitaille 2003), where, by 2005, births outside marriage reached nearly 60 percent, up from approximately 10 percent in 1978 and less than 5 percent in 1951 (Le Bourdais and Lapierre-Adamcyk 2008, 85). Some Quebec judges have creatively conferred use of the matrimonial home on one de facto spouse on the basis of the childrenâs interests.61 Such orders show a judicial refusal to accept that the legislatureâs preference for recognizing relationships on a formal basis should confine the scope for instrumental effects where children are involved. Still, it would be preferable for provincial legislatures to debate the matter and to regularize such a possibility (TĂ©trault 2008, 337).
Another factor is the privileged place of marriage as a point of reference. Indeed, the legal treatment of unmarried couples and same-sex couples has remained closely tied to the regulation of marriage, despite Canadian family lawâs distinction as a frontrunner in recognizing the so-called functional family (Bala 1994; Millbank 2008b). Paradoxically, the response to the fact of greater pluralism in family form has been to treat more couples like married spouses (and more adults like parents). Yet the foundational category of marriage has passed largely unexamined (Polikoff 2008), though it remains the touchstone by which recognition of other relationships is measured and designed. Claims under the equality guarantee in the Charter, in fact, have solidified this approach, arguing that one group (unmarried couples, same-sex couples) is really the same as another group (married couples) and that governments should treat them as such. The policy question is typically framed in terms of a relationshipâs assimilation into marriage, either total (in the case of samesex couples) or partial (in the case of unmarried cohabitants, for support but not for property). This approach, which Bottomley and Wong call a âlogic of semblanceâ (2006, 42), allows little space in which to examine the needs and vulnerabilities flowing from a particular kind of relationship, viewed without reference to marriage.
The idea of treating additional categories of relationship partly or wholly like marriage has some negative effects on thinking about family, since features of the marriage model can be obstacles to identifying other relationships. More specifically, the privileged place of marriage as point of departure for policy analysis imposes three constraints on analysis. One constraint is conjugality: a focus on sexual intimacy makes it harder for policy-makers to assess nonconjugal relationships, such as, for instance, that of cohabiting siblings, for possible recognition as a family unit (Law Commission of Canada 2001).62 Policy analysis of cohabiting siblings or friends necessarily would separate the dimensions of public and private law as well as instrumental and symbolic purposes. In that case, concern for autonomy might well dictate that registration, as opposed to ascription, is most appropriate. And it might be that interpersonal duties and recognition by public programs â such as survivorsâ benefits and tax exemptions for transfers of registered savings â matter more than a symbolic recognition.63
A second constraint the marriage model imposes on thinking about family policy is cohabitation. Researchers are just beginning to focus on couples âliving together apartâ â that is, partners who regard themselves as committed to each other but do not share a dwelling (Haskey and Lewis 2006). Still, even the most creative policy thinking about relationships often assumes cohabitation as an essential criterion. Douglas, Pearce and Woodward challenge this assumption, arguing that, if âfunctionâ is the basis of the claim for legal recognition, there is no adequate basis for excluding noncohabiting partners from protection: âconfining a remedial jurisdiction to those living together re-imposes a type of âformâ as the qualifier for inclusion, creating a new âstatusâ of cohabitation and bringing us back to where we startedâ (2009, 29).
A third constraining feature of the marriage model is its all-or-nothing character, since its full legal effects attach immediately on celebration. Proxies for the commitment of marriage typically copy this on/off character â an unmarried couple either qualify for assimilation into the spousal-support regime applicable to married couples or they do not. Where the legislature has set a threshold of three yearsâ cohabitation, couples having lived together for a shorter time are invisible for legal purposes,64 while couples who cross the three-year threshold come suddenly into view. Yet a less blunt, more incremental approach might better advance the policy objectives associated with unmarried couples. Barlow and James (2004) argue that the commitment and economic reliance of unmarried couples deepens over time; it thus might be more appropriate for legislatures to ascribe duties incrementally, with increasing weight at several intervals or with the arrival of children. More sophisticated policy solutions might come from empirical study of the lives of unmarried couples, as Lewers, Rhoades and Swain (2007) suggest. Unlike the equality claim in Walsh or the 2009 challenge by the Montreal woman, such an approach would not take the form of a constitutional claim for access to marriage by unmarried couples seen as a single group.
Policy analysis also must take account of the diversity of unmarried couples. In 2006, common-law unions were more predominant, in absolute numbers, among individuals ages 25 to 29, although the most rapid growth of this form of family life between 2001 and 2006 occurred in older age groups, with the number of individuals ages 60 to 64 in unmarried, cohabiting couples rising by 77.1 percent (Milan, VĂ©zina, and Wells 2007, 20-1). These two groups likely have very different needs, concerns and goals in not getting married. Some feminists also express caution about assuming that treating unmarried couples like married ones will produce an overall improvement in the situation of women (Bottomley and Wong 2006).
Rigorous attention to the different roles of family law and its private and public aspects is necessary for understanding the logic of reform and for avoiding perverse policy consequences. The strategic shifts evident in past advocacy for same-sex couples are revealing. When the objective was access to a regime of ascription, advocates advanced concern about addressing the economic vulnerability resulting from intimate relationships, and focused on the need to palliate, ex post, the fallout of reliance and investment in such relationships. They argued that the interests of the economically weaker members of same-sex couples aligned with those of the economically weaker members of unmarried, opposite-sex couples, who might not have had a meaningful choice about the status of their relationship. Once the Supreme Court of Canada required the inclusion of same-sex couples within the class of unmarried couples for support purposes, however, the discourse of gay advocacy shifted. Now, the objective became marriage, and advocates for same-sex rights took up the liberal language of choice consistent with an intentional, formal model of regulation, framing the push for same-sex marriage as a quest for the right to choose to marry, focusing on formal recognition resulting from an ex ante choice (Osterlund 2009). That divergence between same-sex couples and unmarried opposite-sex couples shows that those seeking equality under the Charter may not always share common interests (Leckey 2007a, 82-3).
The experience of same-sex couples invites caution on the part of policy-makers in redesigning private and public programs in response to equality claims. Following the federal amendments, individuals living with same-sex partners may have been surprised to learn that they were suddenly âspousesâ for the purposes of various redistributive programs. Lahey (2001) shows that extending spousal treatment to lesbian and gay couples for federal income taxation, social assistance and retirement programs resulted in disproportionately higher taxes and reduced social benefits for those lesbian and gay couples with the lowest incomes. Thus, the net impact of the recognition that same-sex couples âachievedâ may have been regressive in the sense of disadvantaging lower-income couples and benefiting higher-income ones (Young and Boyd 2006). To some extent, therefore, it appears problematic to justify, on the symbolic grounds of equal recognition, the application of redistributive rules to same-sex couples on a functional basis.
The larger point is that it is worth analyzing claims for changes to family law rigorously to see (a)Â whether the objective is instrumental or symbolic and (b) whether the proposed basis for recognition is formal or functional. Policy responses should pursue coherence in the sense that a new measure should be justifiable in the same dimension of family law that it aims to advance. Accordingly, after considering the position of unmarried couples with children and the vulnerabilities that arise when their relationships break down, one can draw two recommendations. First, all the provinces should regularize a mechanism by which a parent with custody of children can secure an order for temporary possession of premises that have been used as the family home, irrespective of which partner owns or rents it. Concerns about autonomy and consent have least application here, because the children have neither chosen nor consented to the marital status of their parents. The second recommendation, which is based on the economic vulnerability of women with children, is that Quebec should provide for an obligation of support between de facto spouses who have a child together.
Both recommendations are instrumental in the sense that they aim to palliate vulnerability, and they are justifiable on functional bases. Neither recommendation has as its aim the symbolic validation of the worth of unmarried couples; moreover, given their limited scope, neither follows the logic of semblance by assimilating a category of relationship into marriage. Restricting the obligation of support recommended for Quebec to unmarried couples who have had a child together would take account of the diversity of unmarried couples. For example, such an obligation would not affect childless cohabitants in their twenties who are roughly equal in their economic position. Nor would it interfere with the economic relations of older cohabitants, such as those who have already been married and divorced and wish to avoid the legal consequences of marriage. In any case, this indication that the position of adult relationships cannot be considered without reference to the presence of children leads to the next section, which addresses directly the legal relations between parents and children.
Legal parentage or filiation is the relationship of parent to child in virtue of which laws attach rights and obligations. Unsurprisingly, parentage has complex effects within family law and policy. It directly engages three crucial oppositions: private versus public family law, instrumental versus symbolic recognition and formal versus functional bases for identifying family relationships. Consequences attach to parentage and filiation within the private law of the family in the form of parentsâ and childrenâs reciprocal rights and duties as well as parentsâ responsibilities and powers vis-Ă -vis their children. Within the public law, governments take parental bonds into account in a number of ways, from tax credits to reducing welfare entitlements. Parentage and filiation operate instrumentally, for distributive purposes, and also symbolically, in the sense of the intrinsic worth of the parental bond.65 Formal and functional bases play out in complex ways. A formal basis for recognition of a parental bond operates in, for example, the registration of a declaration of birth. Functional bases for recognizing a parent-child relationship operate in two ways. One is that some means of establishing the full legal status of parentage or filiation are functional â for example, acting like a parent can lead to a presumption that a person actually is a parent. The other way is that, without leading to parental status, functioning as a parent can also lead to the conferral of some parental rights and duties.
Historically, childrenâs status reflected their parentsâ relationship. Until the 1970s, the marital status of the parents determined the childâs legal status: children born to married parents were âlegitimate,â while those born to unmarried parents were âillegitimateâ and suffered social stigma and legal disadvantages. In some circumstances, illegitimate children could claim support from their parents, but could not inherit from an intestate succession, nor did they become members of the larger family defined by kinship. That state of affairs showed legislatures responding, in a functional way, to the support needs of illegitimate children while withholding from them kinshipâs symbolic recognition. By the 1960s, however, the percentage of illegitimate living births began to rise sharply (see figure 2), and in the 1970s and 1980s, legislatures abolished the status of illegitimacy.66 Filial bonds now connect children directly to parents, largely unmediated by marriage â that is, childrenâs parentage can be determined without reference to their parentsâ marital status; moreover, the content of parental duties does not depend on marital status.
Meanwhile, the early twentieth century had witnessed the enactment of adoption statutes.67 One of adoptionâs initial functions had been to fold illegitimate children into legitimate families. Another had been to provide families for the numerous abandoned children living in religious or other institutional care (LavallĂ©e 2005; Roy 2006b). It took several stages of legislative amendment for legislatures to establish that adopted children are full members of their adopted families. Initially, there was resistance to viewing adopted children as fully equal to those born within marriage. Now, however, adoption produces the full effects of ânaturalâ parentage. It thus pursues both an instrumental policy of providing security for children and a symbolic policy of validating the relationship as a legal family bond.68
The move toward âopenâ adoptions, by which a child comes to know his or her birth parents as well as the adoptive parents, shows legislatures responding to the inclination formally to recognize and functionally to make space not only for the adoptive parents, but also for the genetic parents. For example, Ontarioâs adoption regime now provides for âopenness ordersâ and âopenness agreements,â measures that contemplate continuity in the childâs relationships both before and after adoption.69 Given the role of agencies run or sanctioned by government in assessing prospective adoptive parents and placing children, adoption straddles the line between the private and public law of the family.
The dominant discourse and paramount consideration for decision-making regarding children has changed from one of paternal and then parental rights to one of the best interests of the child (Deleury and Goubau 2008, paras. 635-7).70 An open-textured concept, best interests serves as a vessel into which judges in individual cases must pour content. As with spousal support, decisions regarding children take legislated rules as the point of departure, but case law plays a significant role, and trends in judicial interpretation can rise and fall while the authorizing text remains unchanged. Legislatures and judges, however, are working to balance the competing pulls of family lawâs multiple dimensions, public and private, instrumental and symbolic, formal and functional.
This section first addresses the establishment of legal parental status. It then outlines the effects of parenthood, focusing on the case of family breakdown. Finally, it examines the possibilities for recognizing the effects of parentage on the part of individuals who do not have full parental status. This last issue, like the treatment of adult relationships outside marriage, reveals the grip of the past, in the sense that the traditional legal concept â filiation and parentage in this section, marriage in the preceding one â conditions the analysis. More often, claims are made for assimilation into parental status than for creating a distinct, additional position.
The rules for identifying parent-child relationships are in flux. By and large, legislatures have not kept pace with changes in family practices. Where legislatures have not adjusted the rules or organizing concepts, judges have been required to fit new forms of parenting into the existing framework (Campbell 2007).
As table 6 shows, the Civil Code of Québec recognizes three models of filiation; in Ontario, there are two models of parentage, as set out in table 7. The models may appear conceptually clear, but the means of proving filiation and establishing parentage combine to produce a picture much more complicated than these paradigmatic cases. Collectively, they reveal attention to at least three major factors: genetic connection, intention to parent and the preservation of family stability. Indeed, recent developments show a simultaneous intensification of both genetic connection and intention as foundations of the legal tie between parents and children (Bainham 2008; Millbank 2008c). The legislative aim for filiation or parentage to recognize a genetic connection is perhaps plainest when a judge declares a man to be the father on the basis of DNA evidence. The registration as mother of a woman who has just given birth to a child probably reflects a focus on genetic connection, although it may also reflect intention in the act of gestation.
As for intention as the basis of a parental bond, a clear instance is a judgment of adoption declaring a person to be a parent or a couple to be parents. Further examples are a womanâs declaration of herself as a childâs second mother in virtue of assisted procreation in Quebec or as an âother parentâ in a case of assisted conception in Ontario. Recognition of intention as the basis for parentage, in these last two instances, is consistent with the theory of adoption. These new means of recognizing the second parent of a child born by assisted conception are, however, more direct than adoption in that they do not require judicial proceedings and a determination that the parentage sought serves the childâs best interests.
Other means of establishing parentage or filiation show the legislative concern to protect family stability. Consider the presumption of paternity on the basis of a formal legal status, marriage or civil union, connecting a man to a childâs mother. Admittedly, the ruleâs primary justification may be genetic connection â given the marital duty of fidelity, it may be reasonable to presume that a womanâs husband or civilunion spouse fathered her child. But such presumptions also reveal concern, irrespective of genetic âtruth,â to protect the stability of established families, as well as to place parental duties on the person likeliest to perform them.71
The regimes in Quebec and Ontario thus show a mingling of genetics, intention and caring as bases for recognizing someone as a parent, but they differ in the extent to which the form of enacted rules makes this mingling plain.72 Beyond this snapshot of complexities and contradictory tendencies in the current rules, four issues with respect to parental status call for further discussion: reproductive technologies, parenting by same-sex couples, intentional single parenting and the presence of three parents.
Provincial laws typically do not provide for the full set of disputes arising from the use of reproductive technologies and the parenting practices of Canadian families. Lawmakers have long tolerated a distinction between the legal father and the biological father (Eichler and McCall 1993). In contrast, legal drafters have typically assumed that the childâs legal mother will be unproblematically the biological mother. But assisted reproductive technologies now demonstrate that this assumption is artificial and inadequate (Bainham, Day Sclater, and Richards 1999). Providing the egg, carrying the child and commissioning this process are now separable acts that different women may perform in a given instance. Technology thus introduces the possibility that two or three women may have a claim to be the same childâs legal mother. Such possibilities press lawmakers and judges to determine more precisely âwhat is a parentâ (Jackson 2006). Disputes can arise, for example, when an infertile heterosexual couple obtain an outside contribution for some component of reproduction and the arrangement collapses, calling parentage into question.
Given the reticence of legislatures, courts are left struggling to balance intention to become a parent, the social fact of having given care and genetic links to a child (Boyd 2007; Millbank 2008a,c). Litigation, the outcome of which may be largely unpredictable, can be costly and divisive. Thus, legislatures that have not yet done so should examine their law of parentage and amend it as necessary to reflect established practices using assisted conception. As Moore observes, it is important that lawmakers attend not only to the freedom of adults to have children, but also to the best interests of children (2003, 75).
A child may have two legal parents of the same sex via several different routes, though not all of these avenues are available in every province. A same-sex couple may adopt a child together73 or a child, one of whose parents is in a same-sex relationship, may be adopted by the parentâs partner. In some provinces, a gay male couple may commission a child from a surrogate mother.74 In Ontario, one member of a lesbian couple may become pregnant by anonymous donor sperm and both partners may register themselves as parents on the declaration of birth. Furthermore, in Quebec, a comprehensive regime enacted in 2002 sets up a presumption of parentage on the part of the married or civil-union spouse of a woman who gives birth via a âparental project,â which exists when spouses agree to have a child together using a genetic donation from someone else (Moore 2002a; Kirouack 2005; Leckey 2009c).75 Whatever the social practices of gay men and lesbians who become parents, these scenarios preserve what Kelly (2004) calls a ânuclearâ model: the constraint that, in law, a child can have at most two parents.
In the case of lesbian couples, difficulties may occur if a known genetic father asserts paternity contrary to an earlier agreement that he would be a mere donor (Boyd 2007). There can also be problems where a lesbian couple have a child with a known donor and later wish for the woman not yet a mother to replace the father as second parent by adopting the child. In 2009, in M.A.C. v. M.K.,76 the Ontario Court of Justice refused to dispense with the fatherâs consent so as to erase his bond of parentage in favour of the motherâs partner (Kari 2009).
Several legal possibilities may lead to a childâs having just one legal parent â for example, an individual may adopt a child.77 Moreover, the possibilities for a woman to bear a child for whom she will be the sole parent vary from jurisdiction to jurisdiction. A woman may give birth and declare no father, whether she knows the genetic father or, as in the case of anonymous donor sperm, she does not. Quebecâs rules on filiation are explicit that a woman may intentionally become a single mother, even where the genetic father is known, so long as he consents to being a mere genetic donor.78 Family regimes in other provinces may be less receptive to intentional solo parenting, so that, if a woman who is a childâs sole parent seeks public income support, government agencies may attempt to identify a father from whom to exact child support. Alberta courts, for example, have refused to accept as binding a joint declaration by a woman who had conceived her child by donor sperm, and her male conjugal partner, that parental duties and status would never be ascribed to the male partner (Cossman 2007).79
As a policy matter, should rules of family law facilitate the creation of single-parent families? There are competing considerations. On one hand may be a womanâs autonomy to define the contours of the family into which she brings and raises a child; this interest may include raising a child without legal ties to a man (Boyd 2007). On the other hand may fall concerns about burdens on the social system and the best interests of the child, especially given the poverty rate of families headed by a single mother. Presumably the risk of inadequate resources is higher if, from the outset, only one adult, not two, owes support to the child. Arguably, the paths leading to intentional single parenting by conception are distinguishable from single-parent adoption: the adopted child already exists and lacks a family with adequate resources.
New parenting practices are putting strain on lawmakersâ assumption that a child should have at most two parents. In A.A. v. B.B.,80 an Ontario court declared one child to have a third legal parent. A lesbian couple and a man had planned the conception of the child and were raising him amicably. All parties wished for the partner of the birth mother to obtain parental status. Adoption would have required the fatherâs consent and erased all connections between the child and the paternal relatives, including the father himself. At trial, the judge found that the childâs best interests militated for the legal recognition of his second âmother.â The Court of Appeal determined that the legislatureâs failure to consider same-sex parenting when it overhauled the law of parentage in the 1970s had resulted in a legislative gap. It exercised its inherent jurisdiction to fill this gap by granting the declaration sought. Media coverage emphasized the departure from the traditional view that a child could have no more than two parents (Hanes 2007; Lai 2007). Legal scholars, by contrast, have rightly noted its limited effect as precedent (Bouchard 2007; LaViolette 2007), and the court did not interpret the legislation as providing any general entitlement to such recognition. Future applicants in analogous circumstances would have to prove that recognizing a third parent served that childâs best interests.
Predictably, Ontarioâs âthree parentsâ case has generated varying reactions. Some scholars, with relief, read Quebecâs rules on filiation as precluding such an outcome (PrĂ©mont 2007).81 While facts such as those in A.A. v. B.B. may be relatively rare, they point to the need for creative policy work so as sensitively to recognize relationships between adults and children excluded by family lawâs categories of parentage.
Legal duties connecting parents to their children are identical whatever the model of filiation or parentage and whether or not a childâs parents are together. Rules setting out parental duties appear in provincial laws and in the federal Divorce Act. Where parents live together, it might be supposed that little thought is given to their legal duties, since performance of such duties is often understood as intrinsic to the carrying out of family life. It is typically where an intimate relationship between the parents has broken down, or never existed, that the place for legal enforcement of parental duties is greater.
To give a sense of the prevalence of these cases, a substantial minority of Canadian families (15.6 percent) consisted of lone-parent families according to the 2006 census; within that group, approximately 30 percent of the lone parents were divorced and another 30 percent had never married (Milan, VĂ©zina, and Wells 2007, 8, 15). Where a childâs parents do not live together, the allocation of custody can be a major issue.
Parents may agree as to where the child will live and how they will exercise their rights and carry out their obligations. The vast majority of divorcing parents negotiate a custody arrangement. Where they cannot agree, however, litigation follows, and a judge will decide who has custody and who has access and on what conditions.82 Gendered rules â preferring maternal custody for young children and paternal custody for older ones â have given way to gender-neutral rules that focus on the best interests of the child. The Divorce Act casts the best interests of the child in general terms, subject to two specifications. One is that a courtâs consideration of custody matters must not address a personâs past conduct (such as adultery) unless it affects that personâs ability to act as a parent.83 The other is the so-called friendly parent rule whereby a court must follow the principle that a child should have as much contact with each spouse as is consistent with his or her best interests. Accordingly, when considering one spouseâs application for custody, the court must consider that personâs willingness to facilitate the childâs contact with the other spouse.84
The legislative regimes say little about the circumstances in which judges should award joint or shared custody. Unlike those in some other jurisdictions, such as Australia (Rhoades 2008), Canadian legislatures have not enacted presumptions of shared care or custody. Nevertheless, a change in judicial practice is observable. In 1980, where custody of dependants was determined through divorce proceedings as opposed to by parental agreement, it was awarded solely to the mothers in four-fifths (78.2 percent) of the cases; in 2003, custody was awarded solely to the mother in less than half (47.7 percent), and to both spouses in 43.8 percent, of such cases (Milan, VĂ©zina, and Wells 2007, 15; see also Lapierre-Adamcyk 2003). Indeed, Kirouack suggests that the cases show the emergence of a rebuttable presumption favouring shared custody (2007, 722-7).
Absent legislative guidance, courts have developed guidelines for their recourse to shared custody. Judges consider the parentsâ ability to communicate with each other and the absence of conflict between them, the nearness of the parentsâ respective homes and the childâs wishes (Verdon and TĂ©trault 2004, 217-26). Despite some observersâ sense that a presumption favouring shared custody has crystallized, judges insist that they focus on the individualized, context-specific decision that will serve the childâs best interests (Verdon and Charette 2003, 263-4). While it makes decision-making less predictable, such an individualized, discretionary exercise by judges may be appropriate given the diversity of parenting situations and the bluntness of legislated presumptions (Gilmore 2006). Moreover, some research indicates that a childâs flourishing depends less on the structure of custody than on the family environment. The presence or absence of conflict between separated parents is a key factor (Otis and Otis 2007; Rhoades 2008). As TĂ©trault observes, shared parenting is no panacea (2006, 145).
Data on the living arrangements of recently divorced or separated mothers and fathers provide a snapshot wider than the set of custody disputes in divorce proceedings. The 2006 census revealed that 30 percent of recently divorced or separated fathers and 66 percent of recently divorced or separated mothers were lone parents (Lochhead and Tipper 2008, 10). Moreover, although four-fifths (80.1 percent) of loneparent families consisted of women and their children, the proportion of lone-father families was increasing faster than that of lone-mother families, which Milan, VĂ©zina, and Wells suggest is due in part to the decrease in awards of sole custody to mothers and the increase in joint-custody arrangements (2007, 9, 15). At the same time, looking beyond the effect of legislation and judicial decisions, the increased prevalence of shared parenting â especially in cases not involving judges â also may result from wider social change and parentsâ moral sense of appropriate parenting (Laing 2006; Melli and Brown 2008).
In addition to custody, parents have a legal obligation to support their children in a way that is commensurate with their income. While provincial laws and the federal divorce statute regulate its performance, the duty exists independently of any statute or court order. Consequently, where a parentâs income increases, the content of his or her child-support obligation increases, even if a previous order, based on past income, had fixed the support owed (TĂ©trault 2008, 342-70).85 As in most comparable countries, the duty does not depend on the marital status of a childâs parents (Skinner and Davidson 2009, 34-5).
Legislatures have made varying choices in setting the duration of this duty â for example, it may cease on the childâs reaching the age of majority or it may persist through full-time post-secondary studies (PrĂ©mont 2001). Acting on concerns to increase fairness and reduce transaction costs, legislatures have moved away from discretionary rules by imposing mandatory guidelines for child support.86 This move is part of an effort to increase the rate of payment by support debtors, an effort thought by some to imply a greater parental responsibility for the upbringing of children and a lesser role for the state (Mossman 1997; Robson 2008). Under the Federal Child Support Guidelines, noncustodial parents pay child support to custodial parents based on the formerâs income. For each province, the guidelines set out support according to the number of children and the income of the paying spouse, subject to factors such as special expenses and undue hardship. While the exceptions show a parliamentary intention to inject flexibility into the regime, they also increase uncertainty and the prospects of litigation.87
Recent decades have witnessed significant reform in the enforcement of private support duties, which falls primarily within the authority of the provinces and territories (Skinner and Davidson 2009). During the 1980s and 1990s, provincial and territorial governments created maintenance enforcement programs (MEPs) to provide administrative support to payers and recipients of child and spousal support. The money collected is paid to the recipient whether he or she resides inside or outside the enforcing province or territory. As of March 2008, 66 percent of cases were in compliance with their monthly support payments in the 10 reporting jurisdictions (Statistics Canada 2009, 5-9). Admittedly, not all support arrangements are registered in an MEP â for instance, of the 517,000 cases of divorce or separation with children with a support arrangement, 190,000 were registered in an MEP (Martin and Robinson 2008, 10). Still, the enforcement regimes in place make serious efforts to ensure that debtors execute their duties of family support.
In principle, custody of a child and the parentsâ obligation of support are conceptually distinct. Yet, as a practical matter, studies suggest a strong positive link between the frequency of a nonresident fatherâs visits with his children and the likelihood that he regularly pays support (Juby et al. 2007). Furthermore, while the Divorce Act does not direct judges to award shared custody, the federal guidelines encourage potential payers of support to seek shared custody by providing that, where a spouse exercises a right of access to, or has physical custody of, a child for at least 40 percent of the time, the support that spouse owes is determined by considering the table amount, the increased costs of shared-custody arrangements and the conditions, means, needs and other circumstances of each spouse and any children.88
Shared custody also requires the parents to determine who will claim the fiscal credits and benefits associated with custody of a child (Vincent and Woolley 2001; Daoust 2005; TĂ©trault 2007a, 469-75). Since 1997, child-support payments have been âtax neutralâ â that is, payers of child support do not deduct it from their taxable income, while custodial parents receiving child support do not declare it in theirs.89 This approach represents what Payne and Payne (2006, 281) call a âradical changeâ from the former regime, which had allowed the payer to deduct support payments from his taxable income and required the recipient to declare them in hers.
Still, despite this tax neutrality, the private regimes of child support do not operate in isolation from public regimes. Public agencies are concerned with the enforcement of private support obligations. All provinces and territories treat child support as income for determining the amount of monthly social assistance benefits, and benefits otherwise payable to custodial parents may be reduced by the amount of child support (Dufresne 2001). Family members seeking benefits are obligated to exercise their rights to family support; if they do not, the amount of assistance they receive can be reduced by the amount not claimed.90 Moreover, government agencies may require a parent who has already sought child support to enrol the recipient in an enforcement mechanism (Martin and Robinson 2008, 11).
Arguably, parent-child relationships raise policy issues beyond the period during which private support duties operate. For example, young adults increasingly are living in their parentsâ homes: according to the 1986 census, 32.1 percent of young adults ages 20 to 29 lived in the parental home; in 2006, 43.5 percent of young adults did so (Milan, VĂ©zina, and Wells 2007, 28). Moreover, lone-parent families were far likelier than other family structures to have older children at home: the 2006 census found that 10.6 percent of married-couple families and 2.4 percent of common law-couple families had children ages 25 and older at home; by contrast, more than one-fifth (22.2 percent) of lone-parent families had such children at home.
These findings show a practice of family life that differs from the model implicit in the termination of child-support duties when a child reaches the age of majority or completes post-secondary schooling, and policy-makers should consider the implications of this pattern for young adults and their parents. Is further support required to help young adults make the transition to economic independence? What impact does the presence of grown children have on parentsâ ability to direct resources to retirement and other needs? In particular, the incidence of this pattern among single-parent families invites analysis. Is it an entirely positive sign of family solidarity? Or does it suggest that children raised in families headed by single parents have greater difficulty acquiring self-sufficiency and integrating themselves into the workforce?
In addition to the right to custody and the duty to support a child, contemporary family law provides possibilities to recognize a parent-like relationship between a child and an adult who is not a parent. Legislation in every jurisdiction provides that a court may award custody or access to another person in furtherance of the best interests of the child. Such an order, however, does not confer parental status on the individual in question, which confirms that the childâs best interests can trump a parentâs claim to custody derived from formal parental status.91 Though rare â in 2004, only in 50 of 31,764 court decisions of child custody in divorces were children awarded custody to a person other than the husband or wife92 â this legal possibility is symbolically significant. It shows an instrumental willingness to separate custody of the child, determined by reference to the childâs welfare, from the usual sense that parental responsibilities and rights flow from formal parental status and should overlap with it. It also arguably provides courts with an indirect means of recognizing functional bonds of family even where parental status has not been formalized.93 Less drastic and more common are orders granting access to third parties (TĂ©trault 2000). They provide a means to formalize, for example, the right of grandparents to see children even though their former daughter-in-law has custody.
At the same time, most family regimes in Canada obligate someone who has acted like a parent toward a child (a de facto parent) to support that child. Exceptions are the provincial regimes of Quebec94 and Nova Scotia.95 Where such rules exist, they use the model of ascription. For example, the Divorce Act states, in subsection 15.1(1), that a competent court may order either or both spouses to pay for the support âof any or all children of the marriage.â Subsection 2(2) of the Act extends the definition of âchild of the marriageâ to include âany child for whom they both stand in the place of parentsâ and âany child of whom one is the parent and for whom the other stands in the place of a parent.â The Act does not, however, define âstanding in the place of a parent,â leaving that task to the courts.96 Where a child lives with an aunt and uncle during their marriage, the child might be regarded as a âchild of the marriageâ and both might be regarded as standing in the place of a parent toward the child. The more common case concerns a step-parent.
This recognition of a person as a de facto parent leads, instrumentally, to the imposition of a duty of support. It does not lead, however, to the formal status of parentage or filiation, with its symbolic value. For example, while legislation regarding intestate successions sets out rights of a deceased personâs children and other relatives, such rules do not provide for a child to inherit from a de facto parent. Moreover, the de facto parentâs duty of support under the Divorce Act is unilateral; by contrast with the reciprocal duty of support in provincial law, it leads to no possibility for the adult to claim support from the child in the future. Such a duty can be understood as justified by the best interests of the child â specifically, the concern to minimize the impact of the breakdown of an adult relationship on the child. The justification must also indicate a further basis for the de facto parentâs liability, perhaps induced reliance and the past relationship between adult and child (Ferguson 2008). Otherwise, it could conceivably serve a childâs best interests to collect resources from any potential payer, whatever his or her relation to the child. Some discussions of the duty of the de facto parentâs obligation draw on the symbolic dimension of recognition (Harvison Young 2000). Fallback on legal enforcement is only necessary, though, where the adult resists paying. It is fair to wonder in such circumstances how much of the relationship remains for the law to affirm.
Such rules come into play on the breakdown of the relationship between the adults. The courtâs role arises if, say, the childâs mother claims support from the de facto parent on the childâs behalf and the adult denies that he stood in the place of a parent. A judicial determination as to whether a person met that standard will consider a variety of factors, but, in essence, the question is whether the adult treated the child as a member of his or her family. According to the Supreme Court of Canada in Chartier v. Chartier,97 once it is determined under the Divorce Act that a spouse has stood in the place of a parent toward a child of the marriage, that spouse is subject to the same duty of support as a parent. The de facto parent, in turn, gains the right to apply for custody or access.98
For a step-parent or other de facto parent to owe child support, it is not necessary for the other parent to be absent, unknown or incapable. The result is that more than two adults may owe support to a given child. The possible recognition of three (or more) adults with a child-support obligation after the breakdown of an adult relationship contrasts sharply with the regimes of parentage, which never contemplate more than two parents. The legislative policy seems to be that the childâs best interests are served by increasing the set of possible payers of support while confining the legal parentage to a model more closely resembling ânaturalâ reproduction, at least as far as the number of parents is concerned.
Without becoming a parent by adoption, an adult may thus accumulate child-support obligations in moving from one blended family to another. The duration of a duty of child support is fixed, prospectively, in relation to the childâs achieving the age of majority. It is not fixed, retrospectively, in relation to the duration of the household within which the payer performed a parental role. Consider a man who marries a woman who has a two-year-old child. On the breakdown of the marriage three years later, he might be found to have stood in the place of a parent and could owe support to the child for more than a dozen years. Such enduring obligations, even after a relatively short relationship, can be problematic given the sequence of relationships that many people experience. The frequency of unions â married or unmarried â in the course of a lifetime is now substantial, as table 8 shows; indeed, 16 percent of recently divorced or separated women and 17 percent of men live in a step-family without children common to the partners of the adult conjugal relationship (Lochhead and Tipper 2008, 10). The frequency of sequential relationships likely makes problematic a policy based on increasing support obligations that survive relationships.
The onerous character of the support duty imposed on de facto parents has led to caution in the years since the Chartier judgment. Rogerson (2001), for example, notes the concern that support duties might attach after a relationship so brief that serious bonding might not have occurred. It has also been suggested that the de facto parental duty is not appropriately recognized where the other biological parent is involved in the childrenâs lives.99 Indeed, Quebec courts, noting the extent to which the Divorce Act departs from the traditional civil law of the family, have called for its restrictive interpretation in that province.100 In 2006, seven years after Chartier, the judgments of lower courts still showed an inconsistent approach (Payne and Payne 290-3).
The differences between the respective provincial regimes and the federal divorce scheme can result in substantially different legal characterizations and duties on the part of similar households. Children living in a blended family have different rights, during their parentâs relationship and afterwards, depending on their province of residence or on whether a parent marries a new partner. In Quebec, one of the exceptions to the trend of recognizing a support duty for de facto parents, although an individual may owe child support after divorce from the childâs parent, an individual living unmarried with the childâs parent does not owe such support. For another example, this time across a provincial boundary, a blended family in Quebec in which the adults are unmarried will produce no support duty on the part of the step-parent, while the same facts in another province might lead to the step-parentâs duty to support the child.
Lawmakers have, instrumentally, pursued childrenâs best interests by providing for custody and access and by ascribing a support duty to de facto parents, but there is arguably room for further innovation. Current regimes attach support duties by recognizing some nonparents as parents. This is plain in the statutory definitions that enlarge the context-specific meaning of âparent.â The logic of the Divorce Actâs regime, as interpreted by the Supreme Court in Chartier, maintains the on/off sense that a person either qualifies as a âparentâ and owes support or does not so qualify and owes nothing. It might be appropriate, however, to delineate an intermediate position between parent and stranger (Leckey 2007c). The rigid use of parentage as the paradigmatic model for recognizing rights and duties on the part of an adult toward a child replicates the pattern of maintaining marriage as the model for regulating adult relationships. An intermediate, less onerous category might serve usefully in the case of blended families, as well as in the case of open adoptions.101 Careful reflection would be required to determine the dimensions of family regulation that such a position should engage. Would it have effects under public law, private law or both? Under the private law of the family, an intermediate position might bring a right to access while subordinating any claim for custody to one by a parent. It might also bring, say, a secondary duty of support enforceable only in the absence or incapacity of the parents. Would there be a symbolic recognition of the relationship with some kind of status and, if so, what would it be called? Would the model be ascription or might it be appropriate for an adult to be able to register to assume this new role? What would be the benefits of such a designation relative to the possible reduction in the autonomy of a childâs legal parents, especially a custodial parent? Such determinations are not easy ones, but family practices and the cases litigated testify that the categories âparentâ and âlegal strangerâ do not adequately capture the set of caring adults in the lives of many children.
As a result of developments in family law over the past few decades, men and women are now formally equal in marriage. At the same time, however, marriage rates have declined, so that fewer couples benefit from the current regimes. Unmarried cohabitants and same-sex couples have acquired increasing legal recognition, but that recognition remains modelled on total or partial assimilation to marriage in a way that can be confining. As for the regulation of relations between adults and children, it remains in crucial respects in the grip of the binary model by which someone is either a childâs parent or a stranger to the child.
This section collects the recommendations made in the preceding discussion regarding some avenues for further legal changes. It then considers the effectiveness of the private law of the family at securing the economic welfare of those individuals to whom it applies, and examines how satisfactorily obligations are enforced and distributions made under the âprivate welfare systemâ of the family (Halley 2001, 110). Finally, underscoring the limits of the model of private support, it sets out elements of an appropriate approach on the part of policy-makers.
Despite the reforms to family law in recent decades, the persistence and growth of diverse forms of family life suggest that further reforms are in order, most of them relating to private family law. The following recommendations appear in the order in which they emerged in the text above.
Although the reforms outlined above ought to improve the well-being of family members, the capacity of the private law to secure such improvement is clearly limited. There is thus a need for complementary public policies. Most significantly, the gap between the formal equality of spouses in the law and the financial positions experienced by men and women mean that families headed by single parents, especially by women, are much less well off than families headed by a couple. This feature of contemporary family life prompts the question as to whether the support obligations of parents and former partners should be enforced more stringently. However, while no system of enforcement is beyond improvement, governments have already overhauled the enforcement of support obligations in recent decades, and it is not evident that stricter enforcement of existing obligations would solve the economic difficulties experienced by families headed by single parents. Indeed, for such families, the absence of an arrangement for support may well be a bigger problem than the failure to enforce one.
The Supreme Court of Canada has enjoined judges to emphasize the compensatory role of spousal support, stating explicitly that, where a needy former partner cannot attain self-sufficiency, marriage places the primary burden of support not on the state, but on the other spouse (Brodeur 2000).102 Still, such an approach has consequences only for the relatively small proportion of families where a respondent spouse can pay significant spousal support. Indeed, most divorces or separations do not involve support arrangements. Between 2001 and 2006, of the roughly 2 million cases of divorce or separation, including the end of unmarried unions, only about a third had an arrangement for support payments in place, although nearly two-thirds of cases involving children had a support arrangement (Martin and Robinson 2008, 10).
As for division of property, such regimes redistribute the assets or the value of assets already held within the marriage, no matter which spouse holds title to them, but they cannot increase the total pool available for the enlarged needs of spouses who are separating to form two households. Part of what the data show is simply the effect of dividing the resources of a twoadult family with children into two households, many of which consist of a mother with children. Altering the distributive rules and enforcement mechanisms, however, fails to tackle the structural problem that, in many cases, the total amount of resources is insufficient to support two households after breakdown. More broadly, formal equalityâs failure to secure substantive or material equality hints at the limits of private family law, which, with its focus on support paid by parents to children and by one spouse to the other following the breakdown of an adult relationship, simply cannot by itself assure the material security of Canadian households.103
The limits of the private law of the family thus lead to recognition of the place for robust social programs (Baker 2006). To that end, policy-makers may wish to take stock of innovations in Quebec respecting daycare and parental benefits (Campbell 2006; Phipps 2006). Such programs can be expected to affect the allocation of tasks between partners during a relationship, thus potentially reducing the womanâs disadvantage if the relationship ends. There is also space for income support, child care and job training to provide more support for single-parent households (Cleveland et al. 2008).
Admittedly, different political views lead to different senses of the appropriate relative weight of private and public support duties, but one can venture a number of guidelines for the design and implementation of public policy that is supportive of contemporary families without presuming a political judgment as to the proper balance. The guidelines begin with public policy as it uses relationships that are already recognized by the private law of the family, but then move toward public policy using definitions of family distinct from the private law. That is, the sequence of these guidelines points to public policy autonomously creating its own definitions of family.
This study has traced major developments in Canadian family law. It has drawn out the pluralism of contemporary family law, in the models of family life and in the ways that laws and programs take notice of them. Contemporary Canada has no singular âfamilyâ and no singular âfamily law.â Though the point is sometimes forgotten, there has always been a gap between the practices of family life and the ideals of family law (Noreau 1999). Now, however, the pluralism is arguably more pronounced. The legal diversity is especially rich within the Canadian federation: federal and provincial orders of government generate rules of family law, and they do so by drawing from two legal traditions, the civil law and the common law.
In presenting changes to marriage and divorce, to adult relationships outside marriage and to relations between parents and children, the study has, descriptively, distinguished different dimensions of family regulation. It has distinguished the private law of the family, which concerns the status and rights and duties connecting individuals to one another, from the public law of the family, through which government programs attach duties and benefits to individuals in the light of their relationships. Thus, the legal recognition of some relationships is asymmetrical: in Quebec, unmarried couples are recognized by the public law of the family but not by the private. The study has also distinguished reasons and bases for recognizing family relationships. Instrumental recognition uses the family relationship so recognized to achieve some purpose, usually a distributive one. Symbolic recognition occurs when a legal status has intrinsic value. As for bases for recognition, formal recognition such as marriage or parentage attaches to a formal status, one that comes into existence at an identifiable moment. Marriage and parentage are examples of formal bases for recognition of relationships, ones engaging instrumental and symbolic dimensions. Each status brings an intrinsically valuable recognition of a legal family bond as well as entailing rights and duties. A functional basis for recognition is the way that individuals have acted toward one another. Lawmakers usually use functional recognition for instrumental purposes, but recognition of relationships on this basis typically does not pursue the symbolic dimension. Thus, the recognition of a support duty on the part of a de facto parent is seen, instrumentally, as serving the best interests of the child; it is not cast as the stateâs affirmation of the bond between adult and child.
These oppositions are not merely descriptive devices. The paperâs argument, normatively, is that these three oppositions have appropriate roles to play in the development of a sound family policy. Moreover, confusion and poor policy can result from a failure to analyze claims and policy concerns and possible solutions by their light. In setting out specific recommendations that aim to reduce potential confusion and incoherence, however, a clarification is in order. Reducing incoherence does not mean the unification of family law or definitions of family relationships; rather, varying instances of contemporary family practices merit legal recognition in some respects but not others. The key mission for policy-makers is to assure that asymmetry or irregularity of recognition is an intended part of a larger policy plan, and not happenstance. Moreover, it is crucial to ensure that individuals understand the consequences of their family relationships so that they can take appropriate steps to protect themselves and those they care for.
As a matter of political theory, a legislature has scope to determine the relative weight of the different dimensions of family law and policy operative within its boundaries. Regarding the basis for recognizing family relationships, the common-law provinces typically show a mix of formal and functional approaches. By contrast, the private law of Quebec favours almost exclusively the formal bases for recognition: consensual marriage or civil union in the case of adult relationships, filiation in the case of adults and children. Recent judgments and disputes hint at implicit limits on the scope of legislative action here. Where social practices and legal definitions of family move too far out of line, it appears that judges will feel pressure and aim to reduce the gap. Thus, as noted, judges in Quebec occasionally use a general rule enshrining the best interests of children in order to reach results not otherwise permitted by the formal bases for family recognition in the Civil Code. Indeed, the striking contrasts emerging from Quebec â between its innovative and robust public policy in family matters and its high rate of unmarried cohabitation, on one hand, and its focus on formally defined families in its private law, on the other â invite further reflection. There must be ways, faithful nevertheless to Quebecâs civil-law tradition, that the private law of the family can better reflect contemporary family life in that province.
The other argument throughout the study has concerned the gap between formal and substantive equality. Legislatures have reformed their family law so as to eliminate gendered distinctions between men and women. The achievement of formal equality in family law represents important progress, one that it is easy to overlook without awareness of how recently things differed so much. Yet, economic equality has not followed, which points to the limits of reforms to the private law as a means to secure the economic wellbeing of Canadian families. Where a household divides into two households on family breakdown, no distributive rule and no enforcement mechanism can tackle the root problem of insufficient overall resources. However important the determination and enforcement of private support obligations, there remains a robust role for public programs.
Alberta Law Reform Institute. 2002. Recognition of Rights and Obligations in Same Sex Relationships, Research Paper 21. Edmonton: Alberta Law Reform Institute.
Allard, Serge. 1987. âLa normalisation incidente des conjugalitĂ©s hors mariage.â In Le droit dans tous ses Ă©tats: la question du droit au QuĂ©bec 1970-1987, edited by R.D. Bureau and P. MacKay. Montreal: Wilson & Lafleur.
Bailey, Martha, Beverley Baines, Bita Amani, and Amy Kaufman. 2005. Expanding Recognition of Foreign Polygamous Marriages: Policy Implications for Canada. Ottawa: Status of Women Canada.
Bainham, Andrew. 2008. âArguments about Parentage.â Cambridge Law Journal 67 (2): 322-51.
Bainham, Andrew, Shelley Day Sclater, and Martin Richards, eds. 1999. What Is a Parent? A Socio-Legal Analysis. Oxford: Hart Publishing.
Baker, Maureen. 2006. Restructuring Family Policies: Convergences and Divergences. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.
Bala, Nicholas. 1994. âThe Evolving Canadian Definition of the Family: Towards a Pluralistic and Functional Approach.â International Journal of Law, Policy and the Family 8 (3): 293-318.
————. 2003. âControversy over Couples in Canada: The Evolution of Marriage and Other Adult Interdependent Relationships.â Queenâs Law Journal 29 (1): 41-102.
Bamforth, Nicholas. 2007. âSame-Sex Partnerships: Some Comparative Constitutional Lessons.â European Human Rights Law Review 2007 (1): 47-65.
Barlow, Anne, and Grace James. 2004. âRegulating Marriage and Cohabitation in 21st Century Britain.â Modern Law Review 67 (2): 143-76.
Beaupré, Pascale, and Elizabeth Cloutier. 2007. Navigating Family Transitions: Evidence from the General Social Survey, 2006. Cat. 89-625-XIE n.002. Ottawa: Statistics Canada.
Besson, Samantha. 2007. âEnforcing the Childâs Right to Know Her Origins: Contrasting Approaches under the Convention on the Rights of the Child and the European Convention on Human Rights.â International Journal of Law, Policy, and the Family 21 (2): 137-59.
Bottomley, Anne, and Simone Wong. 2006. âShared Households: A New Paradigm for Thinking about the Reform of Domestic Property Relations.â In Feminist Perspectives on Family Law, edited by Alison Diduck and Katherine OâDonovan. Abingdon, UK: Routledge-Cavendish.
Bouchard, Donna. 2007. âThe Three-Parent Decision: A Case Commentary on A.A. v. B.B.â Saskatchewan Law Review 70 (2): 459-78.
Bowen, Deirdre M. 2008. âDifferential Power in Intact Same- Sex Families Based on Legal and Cultural Understandings of Parentage.â William and Mary Journal of Women and the Law 15 (1): 1-49.
Boyd, Susan B. 1994. â(Re)Placing the State: Family, Law and Oppression.â Canadian Journal of Law and Society 9 (1): 39-73.
————. 2003. Child Custody, Law, and Womenâs Work. Don Mills, ON: Oxford University Press.
————. 2007. âGendering Legal Parenthood: Bio-genetic Ties, Intentionality and Responsibility.â Windsor Yearbook of Access to Justice 25 (1): 63-94.
Brisson, J.-M., and N. Kasirer. 1996. âThe Married Woman in Ascendance, the Mother Country in Retreat: From Legal Colonialism to Legal Nationalism in Quebec Matrimonial Law Reform, 1866-1991.â Manitoba Law Journal 23 (3): 406-49.
Brodeur, Marie-JosĂ©e. 2000. âLes effets de lâarrĂȘt Bracklow: un support privĂ© pour lâex-Ă©poux en remplacement dâun rĂ©gime public dâassurance maladie?â In DĂ©veloppements rĂ©cents en droit familial, edited by Service de la formation permanente, Barreau du QuĂ©bec. Cowansville, QC: Yvon Blais.
Campbell, Angela. 2005. How Have Policy Approaches to Polygamy Responded to Womenâs Experiences and Rights? An International, Comparative Analysis. Ottawa: Status of Women Canada.
————. 2006. âProceeding with âCareâ: Lessons to Be Learned from the Canadian Parental Leave and QuĂ©bec Daycare Initiatives in Developing a National Childcare Policy.â Canadian Journal of Family Law 22 (2): 171-222.
————. 2007. âConceiving Parents through Law.â International Journal of Law, Policy and the Family 21 (2): 242-73.
Carrington, Christopher. 1999. No Place Like Home: Relationships and Family Life among Lesbians and Gay Men. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Casey, Quentin. 2008. âMany Duos Overlooked in Same-Sex Ruling.â Telegraph-Journal (Saint John), December 1.
Cleveland, Gordon, Barry Forer, Douglas Hyatt, Christa Japel, and Michael Krashinsky. 2008. âNew Evidence about Child Care in Canada: Use Patterns, Affordability and Quality.â IRPP Choices 14 (12).
Conway, Heather, and Philip Girard. 2005. ââNo Place Like Homeâ: The Search for a Legal Framework for Cohabitants and the Family Home in Canada and Britain.â Queenâs Law Journal 30 (2): 715-71.
Cornet, Wendy, and Allison Lendor. 2002. âMatrimonial Real Property on Reserve.â Ottawa: Indian and Northern Affairs Canada.
Cossman, Brenda. 2002a. âFamily Feuds: Neo-Liberal and Neo-Conservative Visions of the Reprivatization Project.â In Privatization, Law, and the Challenge to Feminism, edited by Brenda Cossman and Judy Fudge. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.
————. 2002b. âLesbians, Gay Men, and the Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms.â Osgoode Hall Law Journal 40 (3 & 4): 223-49.
————. 2007. âParenting beyond the Nuclear Family: Jane Doe v. Alberta.â Alberta Law Review 45 (2): 501-13.
Cossman, Brenda, and Bruce Ryder. 1999. âM. v. H.: Time to Clean Up Your Acts.â Constitutional Forum 10 (3): 59-64.
————. 2001. âWhat Is Marriage-like Like? The Irrelevance of Conjugality.â Canadian Journal of Family Law 18 (2): 269-326.
Cullity, M.C. 1972. âProperty Rights during the Subsistence of Marriage.â In Studies in Canadian Family Law, vol. 1, edited by D. Mendes da Costa. Toronto: Butterworths.
Daoust, Gilles. 2005. âFiscalitĂ©, famille et rupture: nouvelles rĂšgles du jeu.â In DĂ©veloppements rĂ©cents sur lâunion de fait, edited by Barreau du QuĂ©bec, Service de la formation permanente. Cowansville, QC: Yvon Blais.
Deleury, Ădith, and Dominique Goubau. 2008. Le droit des personnes physiques, 4th ed., by Dominique Goubau. Cowansville, QC: Yvon Blais.
Dewar, John. 1998. âThe Normal Chaos of Family Law.â Modern Law Review 61 (4): 467-85.
Diduck, Alison, and Katherine OâDonovan, eds. 2006. Feminist Perspectives on Family Law. Abingdon, UK: Routledge-Cavendish.
Douglas, Gillian, Julia Pearce, and Hilary Woodward. 2009. âCohabitants, Property and the Law: A Study of Injustice.â Modern Law Review 72 (1): 24-47.
Dufresne, Lucie. 2001. âLes ententes matrimoniales et les prestataires dâaide de dernier recours.â In DĂ©veloppements rĂ©cents en droit familial, edited by Service de la formation permanente, Barreau du QuĂ©bec. Cowansville, QC: Yvon Blais.
Eichler, Margrit, and Marnie McCall. 1993. âClarifying the Legal Dimensions of Fatherhood.â Canadian Journal of Family Law 11 (2): 197-232.
Emon, Anver M. 2009. âIslamic Law and the Canadian Mosaic: Politics, Jurisprudence, and Multicultural Accommodation.â Canadian Bar Review 87 (2): 391-425.
Ferguson, Lucinda. 2008. âFamily, Social Inequalities, and the Persuasive Force of Interpersonal Obligation.â International Journal of Law, Policy and the Family 22 (1): 61-90.
Fisher, John, et al. 2004. Outlaws and Inlaws: Your Guide to LGBT Rights, Same-Sex Relationships and Canadian Law. Ottawa: Egale Canada.
Galloway, Gloria, and Robert Matas. 2009. âDefence to Invoke Gay Marriage as Polygamy Trial Begins in B.C.â Globe and Mail, January 21, p. A6.
Gavigan, Shelley A.M. 1999. âLegal Forms, Family Forms, Gendered Norms: What Is a Spouse?â Canadian Journal of Law and Society 14 (1): 127-58.
Gavigan, Shelley A.M., and Dorothy E. Chunn. 2007. âFrom Mothersâ Allowance to Mothers Need Not Apply: Canadian Welfare Law as Liberal and Neo-Liberal Reforms.â Osgoode Hall Law Journal 45 (4): 733-71.
Gentleman, Jane F., and Evelyn Park. 1997. âDivorce in the 1990s.â In Statistics Canada Health Reports 9 (2). Cat. 82-003-XPB. Ottawa: Minister of Industry.
Gilmore, Stephen. 2006. âContact/Shared Residence and Child Well-Being: Research Evidence and Its Implications for Legal Decision-Making.â International Journal of Law, Policy and the Family 20 (3): 344-65.
Girard, Philip. 1990. âMarried Womenâs Property, Chancery Abolition, and Insolvency Law: Law Reform in Nova Scotia 1820-1867.â In Essays in the History of Canadian Law, Volume 3: Nova Scotia, edited by Philip Girard and Jim Phillips. Toronto: University of Toronto Press for the Osgoode Society.
Goubau, Dominique, Ghislain Otis, and David Robitaille. 2003. âLa spĂ©cificitĂ© patrimoniale de lâunion de fait: le libre choix et ses âdommages collatĂ©raux.ââ Les Cahiers de Droit 44 (1): 3-51.
Halley, Janet. 2001. âRecognition, Rights, Regulation, Normalisation: Rhetorics of Justification in the Same-Sex Marriage Debate.â In Legal Recognition of Same-Sex Partnerships: A Study of National, European and International Law, edited by Robert Wintemute and Mads AndenĂŠs. Oxford: Hart Publishing.
Hanes, Allison. 2007. âCritics Decry 3 Parents and a Baby: Family Group Calls Ruling âNaked Judicial Activism.ââ National Post, January 4, p. A1.
Harvison Young, Alison. 2000. âThis Child Does Have 2 (Or More) Fathers…: Step-parents and Support Obligations.â McGill Law Journal 45 (1): 107-31.
————. 2001. âThe Changing Family, Rights Discourse and the Supreme Court of Canada.â Canadian Bar Review 80 (1 & 2): 749-92.
Haskey, John, and Jane Lewis. 2006. âLiving-Apart- Together in Britain: Context and Meaning.â International Journal of Law in Context 2 (1): 37-48.
Hetzler, Antoinette. 2003. âCare and Discretion: Welfare States Revisited.â International Journal of Law, Policy and the Family 17 (1): 68-98.
Jackson, Emily. 2006. âWhat Is a Parent?â In Feminist Perspectives on Family Law, edited by Alison Diduck and Katherine OâDonovan. Abingdon, UK: Routledge- Cavendish.
Jacobson, Peter M. 1975. âRecent Proposals for Reform of Family Property Law.â McGill Law Journal 21 (4): 556-88.
Jarry, Jocelyne. 2008. Les conjoints de fait au Québec: vers un encadrement légal. Cowansville, QC: Yvon Blais.
Juby, H., J.-M. Billette, B. Laplante, and C. Le Bourdais. 2007. âNon-resident Fathers and Children.â Journal of Family Issues 28 (9): 1220-45.
Jukier, Rosalie, and Shauna Van Praagh. 2008. âCivil Law and Religion in the Supreme Court of Canada: What Should We Get Out of Bruker v. Marcovitz?â Supreme Court Law Review (2d) (43): 381-411.
Kari, Shannon. 2009. âCourt Backs Parental Right of Known Sperm Donors.â National Post, January 29.
Kasirer, Nicholas. 1999. âIntroductory Note: Familiarity and Formality in the Lexicon of Family Law.â In Private Law Dictionary of the Family and Bilingual Lexicons, by the Quebec Research Centre of Private and Comparative Law. Cowansville, QC: Yvon Blais.
————. 2003. âConvoler en justes noces.â In Lâunion civile: nouveaux modĂšles de conjugalitĂ© et de parentalitĂ© au 21e siĂšcle, edited by Pierre-Claude Lafond and Brigitte Lefebvre. Cowansville, QC: Yvon Blais.
Kelly, Fiona. 2004. âNuclear Norms or Fluid Families? Incorporating Lesbian and Gay Parents and Their Children into Canadian Family Law.â Canadian Journal of Family Law 21 (2): 133-78.
Kirouack, Marie Christine. 2005. âLe projet parental et les nouvelles rĂšgles relatives Ă la filiation: une avancĂ©e ou un recul quant Ă la stabilitĂ© de la filiation?â In DĂ©veloppements rĂ©cents en droit familial, edited by Barreau du QuĂ©bec, Service de la formation perma- nente. Cowansville, QC: Yvon Blais.
————. 2007. âLa jurisprudence relative Ă la garde: oĂč en sommes-nous rendus?â In DĂ©veloppements rĂ©cents en droit familial, edited by Barreau du QuĂ©bec, Service de la formation permanente. Cowansville, QC: Yvon Blais.
Lahey, Kathleen Ann. 2001. The Impact of Relationship Recognition on Lesbian Women in Canada: Still Separate and Only Somewhat âEquivalent.â Ottawa: Status of Women Canada.
Lai, Tim. 2007. âCourt Rules Boy Has Mom, Dad and…Mom.â Toronto Star, January 3, p. A1.
Laing, Karen. 2006. âDoing the Right Thing: Cohabiting Parents, Separation and Child Contact.â International Journal of Law, Policy and the Family 20 (2): 169-80.
Lapierre-Adamcyk, Ăvelyne. 2003. âModalitĂ©s de garde des enfants et roĂâle du tribunal.â IRPP Policy Options 24 (7): 58-62. Montreal: IRPP.
LaSalle, Raymonde. 2000. âLes conjoints de fait et la rĂ©sidence familiale.â In DĂ©veloppements rĂ©cents sur lâunion de fait, edited by Barreau du QuĂ©bec, Service de la formation permanente. Cowansville, QC: Yvon Blais.
LavallĂ©e, Carmen. 2005. Lâenfant, ses familles et les institutions dâadoption: regards sur le droit francçais et le droit quĂ©bĂ©cois. Montreal: Wilson & Lafleur.
LaViolette, Nicole. 2007. âDad, Mom â and Mom: The Ontario Court of Appealâs Decision in A.A. v. B.B.â Canadian Bar Review 86 (3): 665-89.
Law Commission of Canada. 2001. Beyond Conjugality: Recognizing and Supporting Close Personal Adult Relationships. Ottawa: Minister of Public Works and Government Services.
Law Commission of Ontario. 2008. Division of Pensions upon Marriage Breakdown: Final Report. Toronto: Law Commission of Ontario.
Leacy, F.H., ed. 1983. Historical Statistics of Canada, Cat. 11-516-XWE. Ottawa: Statistics Canada.
Le Bourdais, CĂ©line, and Ăvelyne Lapierre-Adamcyk. 2004. âChanges in Conjugal Life in Canada: Is Cohabitation Progressively Replacing Marriage?â Journal of Marriage and Family 66 (4): 929-42.
————. 2008. âPortrait des familles quĂ©bĂ©cois Ă lâhorizon 2020: esquisse des grandes tendances dĂ©mographiques.â In La famille Ă lâhorizon 2020, edited by Gilles Pronovost, Chantale Dumont, and Isabelle Bitaudeau. Quebec: Presses de lâUniversitĂ© du QuĂ©bec.
Leckey, Robert. 2002. âRelational Contract and Other Models of Marriage.â Osgoode Hall Law Journal 40 (1): 1-47.
————. 2007a. âFamily Law as Fundamental Private Law.â Canadian Bar Review 86 (1): 69-96.
————. 2007b. âFollowing Same-Sex Marriage: Redefining Marriage and the Impact for Polygamy.â Les ateliers de lâĂ©thique 2 (1): 30-5.
————. 2007c. âLawmakers Should Create Intermediate Parenting Category.â The Lawyers Weekly, November 9, 11.
————. 2007d. âPrivate Law as Constitutional Context for Same-Sex Marriage.â Journal of Comparative Law 2 (1): 172-91.
————. 2008. Contextual Subjects: Family, State, and Relational Theory. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.
————. 2009a. âCohabitation and Comparative Method.â Modern Law Review 72 (1): 48-72.
————. 2009b. âThick Instrumentalism and Comparative Constitutionalism: The Case of Gay Rights.â Columbia Human Rights Law Review 40 (1): 425-78.
————. 2009c. ââWhere the Parents Are of the Same Sexâ: Quebecâs Reforms to Filiation.â International Journal of Law, Policy and the Family 23 (1): 62-82.
Lefrancçois, Guy. 2005. âĂvolution et rĂ©volutions: derniĂšres tendances jurisprudentielles en droit de la famille.â Cours de perfectionnement du notariat 2005 (1): 3-55.
Lewers, Nareeda, Helen Rhoades, and Shurlee Swain. 2007. âJudicial and Couple Approaches to Contributions and Property: The Dominance and Difficulties of a Reciprocity Model.â Australian Journal of Family Law 21 (2): 123-42.
Lochhead, Clarence, and Jenni Tipper. 2008. âA Profile of Recently Divorced or Separated Mothers and Fathers.â Transition 38 (3): 7-10.
Macdonald, Roderick A. 2003. Access to Justice in 2003 â Scope, Scale, Ambitions. Report prepared for the Law Society of Upper Canada. Toronto.
Macdonald, Roderick A., and Alexandra Popovici. 2007. âLe catĂ©chisme de lâislamophobie.â In La Justice Ă lâĂ©preuve de la diversitĂ© culturelle, edited by M. Jezequel. Montreal: Yvon Blais.
MacDougall, Bruce. 2001. âThe Celebration of Same-Sex Marriage.â Ottawa Law Review 32 (2): 235-67.
Macklin, Audrey. 2005. âMulticulturalism in a Time of Privatization: Faith-Based Arbitration and Gender Equality.â Canadian Diversity 4 (3): 75-9.
Martel, Carolyn. 2003. âLes rĂ©gimes de retraite et le partage du patrimoine familial.â In DĂ©veloppements rĂ©cents en droit familial, edited by Service de la formation permanente, Barreau du QuĂ©bec. Cowansville, QC: Yvon Blais.
Martin, Chantal, and Paul Robinson. 2008. Child and Spousal Support: Maintenance Enforcement Survey Statistics, 2006/2007. Ottawa: Canadian Centre for Justice Statistics.
Martin, Craig. 1998. âUnequal Shadows: Negotiation Theory and Spousal Support under Canadian Divorce Law.â University of Toronto Faculty of Law Review 56 (1): 135-59.
Matas, Robert. 2009. âPolygamy Charges in Bountiful.â Globe and Mail, January 8, p. A1.
Meissner, Dirk. 2009. âPolygamy Charges Will Test Boundaries of Religious Freedom, Law Professor Says.â Globe and Mail, January 10, p. S3.
Melli, Marygold S., and Patricia R. Brown. 2008. âExploring A New Family Form â The Shared Time Family.â International Journal of Law, Policy and the Family 22 (2): 231-69.
Milan, Anne, Mireille VĂ©zina, and Carrie Wells. 2007. Family Portrait: Continuity and Change in Canadian Families and Households in 2006. Cat. 97-553-XIE. Ottawa: Statistics Canada.
Millbank, Jenni. 2008a. âThe Limits of Functional Family: Lesbian Mother Litigation in the Era of the Eternal Biological Family.â International Journal of Law, Policy and the Family 22 (2): 149-77.
————. 2008b. âThe Role of âFunctional Familyâ in Same-Sex Family Recognition Trends.â Child and Family Law Quarterly 20 (2): 1-28.
————. 2008c. âUnlikely Fissures and Uneasy Resonances: Lesbian Co-mothers, Surrogate Parenthood and Fathersâ Rights.â Feminist Legal Studies 16 (2): 141-67.
Moore, BenoiĂât. 2002a. âLes enfants du nouveau siĂšcle (libres propos sur la rĂ©forme de la filiation).â In DĂ©veloppements rĂ©cents en droit familial, edited by Service de la formation permanente, Barreau du QuĂ©bec. Cowansville, QC: Yvon Blais.
————. 2002b. âLâunion homosexuelle et le Code Civil du QuĂ©bec: de lâignorance Ă la reconnaissance?â Canadian Bar Review 81 (1): 121-52.
————. 2003. âQuelle famille pour le XXe siĂšcle?: perspec- tives quĂ©bĂ©coises.â Canadian Journal of Family Law 20 (1): 57-97.
Mossman, Mary Jane. 1997. âChild Support or Support for Children? Re-thinking âPublicâ and âPrivateâ in Family Law.â University of New Brunswick Law Journal 46 (1): 63-85.
Mrozek, Andrea. 2009. âIf Couples Want the Legal Protections of Marriage, Then They Should Get Married.â Gazette (Montreal), January 23.
Noreau, Pierre. 1999. âNotions juridiques et rĂ©alitĂ© sociale: un eternel divorce ou un divorce nĂ©cessaire? â le cas du droit de la famille.â Revue Juridique ThĂ©mis 33 (2): 307-25.
Osterlund, Katherine. 2009. âLove, Freedom and Governance: Same-Sex Marriage in Canada.â Social & Legal Studies 18 (1): 93-109.
Otis, Rodrigue, and Catherine Otis. 2007. âLa garde partagĂ©e dans la presse scientifique: symphonie ou cacophonie?â Canadian Journal of Family Law 23 (2): 215-51.
Payne, Julien D., and Marilyn A. Payne. 2006. Canadian Family Law, 2d ed. Toronto: Irwin Law.
Peritz, Ingrid. 2009. âWoman Seeking Alimony after Common- Law Marriage.â Globe and Mail, January 20, p. A4.
Phipps, Shelley. 2006. âWorking for Working Parents: The Evolution of Maternity and Parental Benefits in Canada.â IRPP Choices 12 (2).
Pineau, Jean, and Marie Pratte. 2006. La famille. Montreal: Thémis.
Polikoff, Nancy. 2008. Beyond (Straight and Gay) Marriage: Valuing All Families under the Law. Boston: Beacon Press.
Pratte, Marie. 2008. âLa situation juridique de la famille de 2020: libertĂ©, Ă©galitĂ©, solidaritĂ©?â In La famille Ă lâhorizon 2020, edited by Gilles Pronovost, Chantale Dumont, and Isabelle Bitaudeau. Quebec: Presses de lâUniversitĂ© du QuĂ©bec.
PrĂ©mont, Claudia P. 2001. âObligation alimentaire des parents Ă lâĂ©gard de leurs enfants majeurs: oĂč tracer la ligne?â In DĂ©veloppements rĂ©cents en droit familial, edited by Service de la formation permanente, Barreau du QuĂ©bec. Cowansville, QC: Yvon Blais.
————. 2007. âCommentaire sur la dĂ©cision A. (A.) v. B. (B.) â lâintĂ©rĂȘt supĂ©rieur de lâenfant commande quâon lui reconnaisse deux mĂšres et un pĂšre.â RepĂšres March, EYB2007REP574.
Quebec Research Centre of Private and Comparative Law. 1999. Private Law Dictionary of the Family and Bilingual Lexicons. Cowansville, QC: Yvon Blais.
Rachid, A. 1989. Family Income. Cat. 98-128. Ottawa: Statistics Canada.
Razack, Sherene H. 2007. âThe âSharia Law Debateâ in Ontario: The Modernity/Premodernity Distinction in Legal Efforts to Protect Women from Culture.â Feminist Legal Studies 15 (1): 3-32.
Rhoades, Helen. 2008. âThe Dangers of Shared Care Legislation: Why Australia Needs (Yet More) Family Law Reform.â Federal Law Review 36 (3): 279-300.
Robson, Krista. 2008. ââWrapped in the Flag of the Childâ: Divorced Parentsâ Perceptions of and Experiences with the Federal Child Support Guidelines.â Canadian Journal of Family Law 24 (2): 283-316.
Rogerson, Carol. 2001. âThe Child Support Obligation of Step- Parents.â Canadian Journal of Family Law 18 (1): 9-157.
————. 2004. âThe Canadian Law of Spousal Support.â Family Law Quarterly 38 (1): 69-110.
Roy, Alain. 2001. âLa libertĂ© contractuelle des conjoints de fait rĂ©affirmĂ©e par la Cour dâappel… un avant-goĂ»t des jugements Ă venir?â Revue du Notariat 103 (2): 447-54.
————. 2002a. âLe contrat en contexte dâintimitĂ©.â McGill Law Journal 47 (4): 855-89.
————. 2002b. âLe partenariat civil, dâun continent Ă lâautre.â Revue internationale de droit comparĂ© 54 (3): 759-86.
————. 2006a. âLe contrat de mariage en droit quĂ©bĂ©cois: un destin marquĂ© du sceau du paradoxe.â McGill Law Journal 51 (4): 665-92.
————. 2006b. Le droit de lâadoption au QuĂ©bec. Montreal: Wilson & Lafleur.
Ruru, Jacinta. 2008. âFinding Solutions for the Legislative Gaps in Determining Rights to the Family Home on Colonially Defined Indigenous Lands.â University of British Columbia Law Review 41 (2): 315-48.
Ryder, Bruce. 2008. âThe Canadian Conception of Equal Religious Citizenship.â In Law and Religious Pluralism in Canada, edited by Richard Moon. Vancouver: University of British Columbia Press.
Ryrstedt, Eva. 2006. âFamily Law and Social Law: Reciprocal Dependency in a Comparative Perspective.â International Journal of Law, Policy and the Family 20 (1): 44-54.
Savigneau, Josyane. 2009. âJe ne porte pas de jugement moral sur les choix de vie.â Le Monde, March 21, p. 24. Shachar, Ayelet. 2008. âPrivatizing Diversity: A Cautionary Tale from Religious Arbitration in Family Law.â
Theoretical Inquiries in Law 9 (2): 573-607. Sheppard, Colleen. 1995. âUncomfortable Victories and Unanswered Questions: Lessons from Moge.â Canadian Journal of Family Law 12 (2): 283-329.
Skinner, Christine, and Jacqueline Davidson. 2009. âRecent Trends in Child Maintenance Schemes in 14 Countries.â International Journal of Law, Policy and the Family 23 (1): 25-52.
Statistics Canada. 2003. Topic-based Tabulations: Income of Individuals, Families and Households. Cat. 97F0020XCB2001006. Ottawa: Statistics Canada.
————. 2009. Child and Spousal Support: Maintenance Enforcement Survey Statistics 2007/2008. Cat. 85- 228-X. Ottawa: Statistics Canada.
TĂ©trault, Michel. 2000. âLâenfant et les droits de lâaccĂšs du parent psychologique.â In DĂ©veloppements rĂ©cents sur lâunion de fait, edited by Service de la formation permanente, Barreau du QuĂ©bec. Cowansville, QC: Yvon Blais.
————. 2005. Droit de la famille, 3d ed. Cowansville, QC: Yvon Blais.
————. 2006. La garde partagĂ©e et les tribunaux: une option ou la solution? Cowansville, QC: Yvon Blais.
————. 2007a. âDe choses et dâautres en droit de la famille: la revue annuelle de la jurisprudence 2006- 2007.â In DĂ©veloppements rĂ©cents en droit familial, edited by Service de la formation permanente, Barreau du QuĂ©bec. Cowansville, QC: Yvon Blais.
————. 2007b. La rĂ©daction des conventions en matiĂšre familiale. Cowansville, QC: Yvon Blais.
————. 2008. âDe choses et dâautres en droit de la famille: la revue annuelle de la jurisprudence 2007-2008.â In DĂ©veloppements rĂ©cents en droit familial, edited by Service de la formation permanente, Barreau du QuĂ©bec. Cowansville, QC: Yvon Blais.
Tranter, Kieran, Lyndal Sleep, and John Stannard. 2008. âThe Cohabitation Rule: Indeterminacy and Oppression in Australian Social Security Law.â Melbourne University Law Review 32 (2): 698-738.
Verdon, Jocelyn, and StĂ©phanie Charette. 2003. âLa jurisprudence marquante de la derniĂšre annĂ©e en droit de la famille.â In DĂ©veloppements rĂ©cents en droit familial, edited by Service de la formation permanente, Barreau du QuĂ©bec. Cowansville, QC: Yvon Blais.
Verdon, Jocelyn, and Michel TĂ©trault. 2004. âUne revue de la jurisprudence marquante en 2003-3004.â In DĂ©veloppements rĂ©cents en droit familial, edited by Service de la formation permanente, Barreau du QuĂ©bec. Cowansville, QC: Yvon Blais.
Vincent, Carole, and Frances Woolley. 2001. âLes familles canadiennes et le fisc: une question dâĂ©quitĂ©.â IRPP Choices 7 (3).
Weinrib, Lorraine E. 2008. âOntarioâs Sharia Law Debate: Law and Politics under the Charter.â In Law and Religious Pluralism in Canada, edited by Richard Moon. Vancouver: University of British Columbia Press.
Wright, Wade K. 2006. âThe Tide in Favour of Equality: Same-Sex Marriage in Canada and England and Wales.â International Journal of Law, Policy and the Family 20 (3): 249-85.
Young, Claire F.L., and Susan B. Boyd. 2006. âLosing the Feminist Voice? Debates on the Legal Recognition of Same Sex Partnerships in Canada.â Feminist Legal Studies 14 (2): 213-40.
Robert Leckey is assistant professor in the Faculty of Law, McGill University, and a member of the Quebec Research Centre of Private and Comparative Law. He teaches family law and constitutional law, and he conducts research in those fields as well as in comparative law. A former law clerk at the Supreme Court of Canada, he is the author of the monograph Contextual Subjects: Family, State, and Relational Theory (2008) and of articles published in Canadian, British, and American journals. He has won prizes for best legal article from La Fondation du Barreau du Québec and the Canadian Association of Law Teachers.
This publication was produced under the direction of Sarah Fortin, Research Director, IRPP. The manuscript was copy-edited by Barry Norris, proofreading was by Barbara Czarnecki, production was by Chantal LĂ©tourneau, art direction was by Schumacher Design and printing was by AGL Graphiques.
Copyright belongs to IRPP. To order or request permission to reprint, contact:
IRPP
1470 Peel Street, Suite 200
Montreal, Quebec H3A 1T1
Telephone: 514-985-2461
Fax: 514-985-2559
E-mail: irpp@nullirpp.org
All IRPP Choices and IRPP Policy Matters are available for download at irpp.org.
To cite this document:
Leckey, Robert. 2009. âFamilies in the Eyes of the Law: Contemporary Challenges and the Grip of the Past.â IRPP Choices 15  (8).